The Structure of DP in English and Polish (MA)

background image

KATOLICKI UNIWERSYTET LUBELSKI

JANA PAWŁA II

Wydział Nauk Humanistycznych

Instytut Filologii Angielskiej

Agata Bednarz

nr albumu: 81874

THE STRUCTURE OF DP IN ENGLISH AND POLISH

Praca magisterska

napisana pod kierunkiem

dr hab. Anny Bondaruk, prof. KUL

w Katedrze

Językoznawstwa Teoretycznego

Lublin 2010

background image

2

CONTENTS

List of abbreviations ……..………………………………………………………… 4

Introduction ..………………………………………………………………………. 6

Chapter 1: The DP Hypothesis- Theoretical Background

Introduction…………………………………………………………………….. 9

1.1. The GB analysis of an NP and a clause ...……………………………... 9

1.2. Abney’s DP Hypothesis ...……………………………………………... 16

1.3. Further remarks on the structure of nominal phrases ..……….…….….. 24

Conclusion ..………………………………………………………………… 28

Chapter 2: Functional Projections within the DP

Introduction ……………………………………………………………………. 29

2.1. AgrP - Agreement Phrase ……………………………………………… 30

2.2. NumP – Number Phrase ……………………………………………….. 34

2.3. QP – Quantifier Phrase ……………………………………………….... 36

2.4. The order of adjectives …………………………………………………. 42

2.5. Little n – the nominal shell ………………………………………… …. 45

2.6. DemP – Demonstrative Phrase and PossP – Possessive Phrase ……….. 48

2.7. The hierarchy of functional elements within the DP …………………... 51

Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………... 55

Chapter 3: The DP in Polish

Introduction ……………………………………………………………………. 57

3.1. Is there a DP in Polish? ………………………………………………... 58

3.1.1. Left Branch Extraction (LBE) …………………………………... 59

3.1.2. Double genitive constructions …………………………………... 65

3.1.3. The lack of N-to-D movement …………………………………. .. 66

3.1.4. Other arguments against the DP analysis of Polish nominals …... 68

background image

3

3.2. The internal structure of nominal phrases in Polish …………………… 70

3.2.1. Noun – pronoun asymmetry. The position of personal pronouns .. 71

3.2.2. Adjectives ……………………………………………………...... 73

3.2.3. Possessive and demonstrative pronouns ………………………… 77

3.3. The structure of Polish nominal phrases ………………………….......... 79

Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………... 81

Summary and conclusions ………………………………………………………... ... 83

References ………………………………………………………………………....... 88

background image

4

List of Abbreviations

1

st

– first person

2

nd

– second person

3

rd

– third person

A – Adjective

ACC – accusative

Agr – Agreement

AgrP – Agreement Phrase

AP – Adjective Phrase

AUX – auxiliary

C – Complementizer

Class – Classification

ClassP – Classification Phras

Conj – Conjunction

ConjP – Conjunction Phrase

CP – Complementiser Phrase

D – Determiner

DAT – dative

def. – definite

Deg – Degree

DegP – Degree Phrase

Dem – Demonstrative

DemP – demonstrative Phrase

Det – Determiner

DP – Determiner Phrase

ERG – Ergative

EPP – Extended Projection Principle

fem. – feminine

Foc – Focus

FocP – Focus Phrase

GB Theory – the Government and

Binding Theory

GEN – genitive

I – Inflection

IP – Inflection Phrase

K – nominal complementizer

KP – nominal complementizer phrasal

projection

LBE – the Left Branch Extraction

masc. – masculine

n – light noun

N – Noun

NP – Noun Phrase

NOM – nominative

nP – light noun phrase

Num – Number

NumP – Number Phrase

Ø – empty position

Ɵ-role – theta- or thematic role

P – Preposition

pl. – plural

PP – Preposition Phrase

possd – Possessed feature

Q – Quantifier

QP – Quantifier Phrase

sing. – singular

background image

5

Spec. – Specifier

Subj. – subjective

t – trace

Tns. – Tense

UTAH – the Uniormity of Theta Assignment Hypothesis

v – light verb

V – Verb

vP – light verb phrase

VP – Verb Phrase

X – any lexical category

XP – any phrasal category

background image

6

Introduction

The aim of this dissertation is to investigate the structure of nominal expressions

in English and Polish. The thesis examines the syntax of nominal expressions in both

languages and aims at providing a universal representation of nominal phrases. The

starting point for the study is the DP Hypothesis put forward by Abney (1987).

The nominal expression investigated in this dissertation is a constituent headed

by a Noun. Some examples are given in (1) below:

(1) a. Mary is a student.

b. This is a big black dog.
c. The existence of DP in articleless languages is controversial.

All the expressions in italics given in (1) belong to a group of nominal phrases.

Although they differ in the degree of complexity, they all share the same syntactic

structure. Following Abney (1987), it is claimed that they are all instantiations of a

Determiner Phrase (DP). They are headed by a functional element D, whose overt

realisation corresponds to either a definite or an indefinite article (in English those are:

a(n)/ the).

Postulating the universality of grammar, it appears necessary to assume that the

same structure applies to all human languages, whether they show some overt

realisation of D or not.

However, a lot of controversies surround the structure of DP. Some of the

queries are listed below:

1. Are nominal expressions consisting of only one word DPs? (e.g. Mary)

background image

7

2. If an article or an empty element constitutes a head of the phrase, what is the

syntactic position of other elements appearing within the phrase, i.e.

Quantifiers, Adjectives, etc.?

3. Why do articleless languages allow syntactic phenomena (e.g. Left Branch

Extraction) disallowed by languages with overt realisations of D?

Those questions and others have been addressed by numerous studies carried on

since the DP Hypothesis first appeared. Data taken from different languages and

different elements of nominal expressions were targeted. However, it is possible to

distinguish two major stands: one extending the DP Hypothesis onto all languages

without exceptions (Abney (1987), Progovac (1998), Migdalski (2000), Sio (2006),

Rutkowski (2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2002c, 2007a, 2007b, 2009), among others), the other

treating the nominals appearing in aricleless languages as traditional NPs (Fukui (1986),

Chierchia (1998), Willim (2000), Kim (2004), Bošković (2003, 2004, 2005, 2008),

among others).

As far as the theoretical model is concerned, this study is based on two linguistic

theories created by Chomsky, i.e. the Government and Binding Theory (Chomsky

(1981)) and the Minimalist Program (Chomsky (2000, 2001)). The lack of a single

framework stems from the fact that a considerable number of important studies on the

structure of nominals has not been carried out with the recently recognised Minimalist

Program, for instance, two works crucial for this study: Abney’s (1987) The English

noun phrase in its sentential aspekt and Rutkowski’s (2007b) Hipoteza frazy

przedimkowej jako narzedzie opisu składniowego polskich grup imiennych.

This dissertation offers an overview of the DP Hypothesis, as well as more

recent interpretations of the structure of nominal expressions. Both approaches toward

background image

8

articleless languages are taken into consideration. Chapter 1focusses on Abney’s (1987)

dissertation, which introduces the idea of DP structure. The goal of this chapter is to

present the DP Hypothesis, all together with its theoretical background. Furthermore,

early analyses of functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP are

outlined and explained.

Chapter 2 provides a survey of more recent approaches to the DP structure. The

major part of this chapter is devoted to various functional projections appearing

between a DP and an NP. This analysis leads to postulating a complete structure of

nominal phrases, which can be applied both to the English and Polish language.

The final chapter focuses on the analysis of the structure of Polish nominals. It

presents two recent approaches to nominal phrases in Slavic languages: one adapting

Abney’s DP Hypothesis to the Polish syntax, the other presenting Polish nominals as

NPs. Taking both approaches into consideration, the structure worked out in the

previous chapter of the study is explained and special attention is paid to the possibility

of adapting it to the Polish syntax. Finally, the complete structure of a DP in Polish is

presented.

background image

9

Chapter 1

The DP Hypothesis - Theoretical Background

Introduction

The aim of Chapter 1 is to introduce the background and core assumptions of the DP

Hypothesis introduced by Stephen Abney in his PhD dissertation, in 1987. On the basis

of cross-linguistic indicators and facts, Abney demonstrates that the classical GB

interpretation of the structure of nominal phrases is flawed. He rejects the idea of a

nominal phrase understood as a phrasal projection of a lexical head – a Noun, and

suggests a new structure – one parallel to the structure of a clause and based on the

functional projection of a Determiner with an NP functioning as its complement.

The basic GB analysis of the structure of nominal phrases, together with syntactic

facts suggesting its explanatory inadequacy is given in section 1. Subsequently, section

2 outlines Abney’s DP Hypothesis, the way it is presented in his PhD dissertation.

Finally, section 3 focuses on further problems with the structure of nominal phrases,

especially concentrating on the position of elements intervening between a Determiner

and a Noun, i.e. Quantifiers, Adjectives, etc.

1.1 The GB analysis of an NP and a clause

The classical GB interpretation of the structure of nominal phrases provides us with

the following phrase maker:

background image

10

(1) NP

D(P) N’

N

XP

As can be seen in (1), the maximal projection of a nominal phrase, the NP,

dominates the intermediate projection N’ and the specifier D(P), the Determiner

(Phrase). The N’, in turn, dominates the zero projection, i.e. the Noun (N) and its

complement, marked as an XP in order to show that it can be realised syntactically by

various types of phrases, for instance PPs.

This structure is built in accordance with the X-bar Theory (Chomsky (1970);

Jackendoff (1977)). The phrase is endocentric – the constituents are projections of a

single head. It observes the Binary Branching Constraint – the higher nodes dominate

only two nodes at once – and the Singlemotherhood Constraint – nodes are dominated

only by one element at the same time.

However, that structure raises numerous questions. The basic one concernes the

status of Determiners. In English, all the elements that may appear under D, i.e.

possessives (possessive pronouns and genitives), demonstratives and articles, remain in

complementary distribution – they cannot co-occur within one phrase, as shown in (2).

(2) a. *the Mary’s description

b. *the her description
c. *Mary’s her description
d. *this the description

(Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 408))

e. this description
f. her description
g. Mary’s description
h. the description

background image

11

The conclusion to be drawn from (2 a-h) is that all Determiners occupy the same

node – D. No clear evidence pointing to the possibility of claiming the existence of the

DP can be found – this fact is reflected by the presence of brackets, which are used to

mark optionality, within the DP in the phrase maker in (1). However, to accept the

possibility that Determiner Phrases do not exist is to accept a strong violation of the X-

bar Theory constraints, which also means accepting the fact that Determiners, as a class,

are possibly not able to project further, take complements or to have proper specifiers. If

this were so, Determiners would be the only exception within all lexical and functional

elements of a language.

What is more, the claim that all elements, traditionally bearing the name of

Determiners, share the same grammatical features turns out not to be true when

confronted with the data in (3a) and (3b) below:

(3) a. Mary’s house

b. the house

my teacher’s house

a house

the woman next door’s house

Ø houses

the French student’s house

this house

the teacher of history’s house

that house

her house

these houses

Thelma and Louise’s house

those houses

(Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 409))

As demonstrated in (3a), possessors are an open class of elements; they are

unlimited and new elements within this class can still appear. On the contrary, articles

and demonstratives, as can be seen in (3b), constitute a closed class – no new elements

can be created. This argument is true cross-linguistically – the restriction with regard to

the number of articles and demonstratives is evident in other languages as well, not only

in English. For instance, in Hungarian there is only one definite article a (Szabolcsi

(1984)). What is more, in comparison with the possessives, articles and demonstratives

background image

12

do not contribute significantly to the descriptive content of the phrase. Articles carry the

[±definiteness] feature, whereas demonstratives indicate the spatial relation between the

speaker and the object being described (Haegeman and Guéron (1999: 410)).

It is also worth noticing that not all languages have a restriction on the co-

occurrencee of possessives and articles or demonstratives, as presented in (4).

(4) a. un mio libro

[Italian]

a my book
‘a book of mine’


b. esas ideas tuyas

[Spanish]

those ideas yours

‘those ideas of yours’

c. cartea ta

[Romance]

(Radford (1988: 171-172))

book-def. your
‘the book of yours’`

d. ten mój pies

[Polish]

this my dog
‘this dog of mine’

The constructions shown in (4) are ungrammatical in English but they are fully

grammatical in Romance and Slavic languages. A possible explanation for this

phenomenon is offered by Radford (1988). He suggests that Determiners can be

attached to the maximal projection of NP and they extend an NP into another NP. This

hypothetical structure is presented in (5) below:

(5) a.

NP

b. NP→ D NP

D

NP

D

NP

background image

13

On the basis of the structure in (5a), it is possible to formulate a phrase structure rule

presented in (5b), saying that an NP immediately dominates a Determiner and another

NP. This is strongly criticised by Radford (1988). A major flaw of this line of reasoning

is that it does not take into consideration the fact that rule (5b) is recursive and hence

can be reapplied indefinitely many times. In accordance with rule (5b), the structures

presented in (6) below would be recognised as grammatical.

(6) a. *the a this my car

b. *mój ten wasz tamten stół

[Polish]

*my this your that table



c. *un mio tuo quello libro

[Italian]

*a my your this book

As can be seen in (6a-c ), a larger number of Determiners within one nominal

phrase is ungrammatical even in Romance or Slavic languages, in spite of the fact that

these languages normally allow the combination of a possessor plus an article or a

demonstrative.

Analysing the notion of multiple determiners presented above, a conclusion may

be drawn that possessors constitute a class of elements different from articles and

demonstratives and, because of this, they need to have a separate position assigned to

them within the construction of a nominal phrase (Haegeman and Guéron (1999)). This

position seems to be missing in the classical structure that treats nominal phrases simply

as NPs with Determiners occupying the position of [Spec; NP].

Further evidence against the structure in (1) stems from a comparison of Nouns

and Verbs understood as two most important lexical classes. In contradistinction to the

questionable structure of a nominal phrase, the GB Theory provides us with a complete

background image

14

and in-depth analysis of verbal phrases. Verbs (and Nouns alike) project maximal

projections – Verb Phrases (VPs) but, above all, they are augmented with functional

projections of an Inflection and a Complementiser. Therefore, the entire clause is

understood as an extended projection of a Verb. This structure is presented in (7).

(7) CP

Spec

C’

C

IP

NP

I’

I

VP

[± tense]

[±agreement] Specifier V’

(Haegeman (1997:18))


V

XP

As can be seen, each lexical or functional element within a clause projects its

intermediate and maximal projection in accordance with the X-bar Theory. The highest

projection of the clause is the CP – the Complementiser Phrase, that dominates its

specifier and C’. The CP is headed by a Complementiser, which carries the illocutionary

force of the sentence and takes the IP – the Inflection Phrase as its complement. The IP

immediately dominates the NP (which fulfils the role of the subject of the clause) and

I’. The I’ dominates the head of the IP. I is the functional element carrying the features

[± tense; ±agreement]. The complement of I is the Verb Phrase –VP, which

immediately dominates its specifier and V.’ VP is headed by a Verb which can take

numerous possible types of complements (for instance: PPs, NPs, CPs, etc.).

The complexity of the structure presented in (8) is even more striking when we

consider the following facts revealing the similarities between nominal and verbal

background image

15

phrases that cannot be explained with the help of the structure in (1). First of all,

Determiners show some features similar to Complementisers (Haegeman and Guéron

(1999)). They constitute a closed class of functional elements and they do not contribute

significantly to the semantics of the sentence. Still, they can introduce the Noun Phrase

and have the [±definiteness] or [±distance] feature.

In addition, there appears another question, this time, based on the analysis of the

semantic projection of a Verb Phrase and a Noun Phrase. According to Chomsky

(1957), each lexical item has its categorial (c-) and semantic (s-) projection. The two c-

projections are an X-bar and an X-double-bar projections of the syntactic unit and the s-

projection is a projection of the meaning of the lexical item. It is worth focusing on the

fact that the s-projection of a verb spreads over the best part of the sentence involving

all of its main elements, i.e. the subject, the predicate and the objects. To put it another

way, the whole clause refers to the action denoted by the verb, other parts of the

sentence, e.g. adverbials, just give some additional information. By way of illustration,

in John is doing homework, the whole clause expresses an action of doing homework.

Here homework constitutes a complement of the verb, whereas John (Specifier of IP)

adds the information about who the Agent is.

In contradistinction to a Verb, a Noun has a narrower-spread s-projection – it is

simply the same as the c-projection of the noun (i.e. NP). Therefore, it affects only

complements enclosed within the NP.

background image

16

1.2 Abney’s DP Hypothesis

The starting point for Abney’s dissertation is an ambiguous construction that could

be understood both as an NP and a clause (Abney (1987: 14-15)). An example of this

construction is shown in (8) below:

(8)

John’s building a spaceship.

That can be paraphrased as follows:

(9) John built a spaceship.

With the meaning illustrated in (9) the structure constitutes the so-called

‘Poss- ing’ gerundive construction, which in its form is similar to a clause, yet it

remains an NP. From the comparison of (8) and the corresponding clause (9) one

may draw the following conclusions, which may later on serve as evidence for the

theory assuming the existence of DPs:

1. The structure of (8) is similar to the structure of (9): John is a subject, building

denotes the action, therefore fulfils the same function as a verb, and a spaceship

is an object.

2. (8), in contrast to (9), is an NP because it has the characteristic distribution of

NPs, i.e. it can function as a [Spec; IP], compare the following examples (Abney

(1987: 15)):

(10) a. *Did [that John built a spaceship] upset you?

b. Did [John’s building a spaceship] upset you?
c. Did [John] upset you?

Putting these two pieces of information together, we obtain a structure as presented

in the P-maker below:

background image

17

(11)

NP

.

NP

VP

John’s

V

NP


building a spaceship

Here the NP John's building a spaceship comprises an NP John’s in the position of

[Spec; NP] and its verbal complement building a spaceship. However, this structure

represents a strong violation of basic conditions on syntactic structure of phrases. First

of all, the Endocentricity Constraint is violated by the fact that the highest NP lacks a

head. Secondly, the structure of NPs John’s and a spaceship is still unclear.

Abney’s solution to this problem is as follows: the structure of noun phrases must be

based on the structure of clauses and it must be headed by an inflectional element. As a

result of this, the Endocentricity Constraint is satisfied and the presence of an overt

gerundive ending ’s is accounted for. The P-maker of an NP structure showing the

similarity to a clause is given in (12b) (Abney (1987:23)).

(12) a. Clause

b. Abney’s nominal phrase

IP

XP

NP

I’

XP

X’


John

John’s

I

VP

X

VP

[Tns, Agr]

[Agr]

V

NP

V

NP

built a spaceship

building a spaceship

background image

18

The head of the nominal phrase is a functional element represented by Agreement

(it has no name by itself because its functions are still not clarified, therefore it remains

marked as an X). The VP building a spaceship is its complement, and John's (another

nominal expression) functions as its Specifier. This structure can be confirmed by

examples from Turkish, especially as far as the inflectional projection hosting Agr is

concerned:

(13) a. el

b. sen-in el-in

c. on-un el-i

you- Gen hand- 2

nd

sg

he-Gen hand-3

rd

sg

‘the/a hand’

‘your hand’

‘his hand’
(Abney (1987:21))

In the examples above a noun acquires the same number and person as the

possessive pronoun preceding it. This strong agreement between the possessor and the

noun in Turkish serves as an argument for the presence of an Agr within the noun

phrase. The logical consequence of this postulate and the fact that within clauses the

Agr feature, always carried by the functional element (I), is required by a functional

element present within an NP and similar to the I.

The idea of the inflectional projection within the noun phrase seems even more

unavoidable in the case of languages like Yup’ik, in which the subject of a noun phrase

is assigned the same Ergative case as the subject of a clause.

(14) a. angute-t kiputa- a- t

the men- Erg buy- Past- it- 3

rd

pl masc

‘the men bought it’


b. angute- t kuiga- t
the men- Erg river- 3

rd

pl masc

‘the men’s river’

(Abney (1987: 39))

background image

19

According to Abney (1987), the mysterious element similar to I and carrying the

Agr feature is in fact a Determiner (D) projecting into a D’ and further on into a DP. His

arguments supporting this hypothesis are as follows (Abney (1987: 75-76)):

1. Determiners are a class of functional elements, therefore they can behave

like modals (which appear under I in IPs) and appear under functional D.

What is more, they are the best candidate for being a carrier of the Agr

feature, similarly to the Inflection within a clause.

2. With the hypothesis applied, it is finally possible to distinguish the

intermediate and maximal projections and pinpoint specifiers and

complements taken by Determiners. As a result, Determiners, as a class, are

no longer defective with respect to the X’- theory.

The representation of this new structure of nominal phrases is shown in the P-

maker below:

(15)

DP

.

DP

D’

John’s

D

VP

Agr

V

NP

building a spaceship

The nominal phrase is presented as a DP headed by a functional D filled by the

Agr. The main DP takes its own specifier and the complement, i.e. the DP John's and

the VP building a spaceship, respectively, this structure works for any kind of nominal

background image

20

expression in English. The space for all pre-nominal elements is provided, and the

presence of Agreement is accounted for and shown within the structure below:

(16)

DP

D’

DP

D

NP

a.

my

Agr

pen

b.

Ø

a

cat

It also accounts for double-modifier structures combining an article with a

possessor (i.e. multiple modifiers presented already on the basis of examples taken from

Romance and Slavic languages in section 1.2. of this chapter), which appear also in

Hungarian. There, the possessor, a determiner, is preceded by another determiner - the

definite article a/az, e.g.

(17) a. Az en vendeg-e-m

the my guest- possd-1

st

sg

‘my quest’


b. a te ismerös- ei- d

the your acquaintance-possd-2

nd

sg

‘your acquaintance’

(Abney (1987: 44))

Here the overt agreement between the possessor and the noun as well as the

appearance of multiple determiners (which were placed by Jackendoff (1977)) within a

treble- bar structure, violating basic constraints of the X-bar Theory) suggests that the

DP hypothesis is in fact true. Not only is there a need for a functional element that

would carry the agreement feature but also there must be a position for the possessive

pronoun that in classical interpretations filled the position of [Spec; NP], i.e.

Determiner. Following Szabolsci (1984), Abney claims that an additional determiner

background image

21

like this appearing in Hungarian is a kind of complementiser K introducing noun

phrases instead of clauses

and projecting into K-bar and K-double-bar (Abney (1987:

44) after Szablocsi (1984)). This fact stresses still more strongly the sentential aspect of

nominal phrases. An example of a Hungarian phrase with a double-modifier and its P-

maker is shown in (18) (cf. (17a)).

(18) KP

K

DP

az

DP

i

D’

en

D

NP.

Agr

i

-m

N

N

j

Agr

j

vendeg- e-

(Abney (1987:44, 251))

What is also worth mentioning, Abney’s DP hypothesis allows us to locate PRO

in a subject position within the noun phrase. This ‘nominal’ PRO functions as an Agent

in cases like (19) below (Abney (1987:92)) e.g.

(19) [

DP

PRO the [

DP

destruction of the city]]

background image

22

Here PRO is assigned a Θ-role via predication – PRO functions as an external argument

of destruction (reflecting the argument structure of clauses). What is more, PRO is also

responsible for licensing rationale clauses embedded within a noun phrase.

(20) the PRO review of the book [PRO to prove a point] (Abney (1987:93))

As can be seen in (20), only when PRO is present is the rationale clause

licensed, because the process of licensing requires the Agent Θ-role realized

syntactically and covert PRO can assume this role.

Another piece of evidence for Abney’s hypothesis is the notion of head to head

movement within the noun phrase, which accounts for post-nominal adjectives in

English. What is more, the NP-internal head-to-head movement reflects another

similarity between CPs and DPs. The head of the NP is claimed to move to the head of

the DP position (the equivalent of V-to- T and T- to- C movements). Due to this fact

adjectives appearing postnominally in English

are not exceptions any more but fit into a

general paradigm

(Abney (

1987: 287)).

(21)

a. a good boy

c. *good someone

b. *a boy good

d. someone good

According to Abney, someone like everyone, anyone, etc., represent

morphological mergers. Every and one are separately merged within an NP and they can

be formed thanks to the movement of one to the D position, which is illustrated in (22)

below:

background image

23

(22)

DP

.

D

NP

D

N

AP

N’

some-one

i

good

N

t

i

In fact, not only have the concepts of PRO and head movement been affected by

the DP hypothesis, but above all, the notion of the determiner has undergone a great

change. Before 1987, the category of determiners included both possessors and articles.

However, after Abney’s dissertation, the status of possessors and pronouns has radically

changed. Abney claims that possessors cannot be determiners because:

1. possessors co-occur with other determiners therefore, they cannot occupy the

same place within the structure of the phrase (Abney (1987: 270)), e.g.

(23) a. in Italian:

un mio libro

‘a my book’

b. in Hungarian: az en ostalem

‘the my table’

2. possessors do not have the same distribution as DPs, as shown in (24):

(24) a. * the car of [Mark’s]

b. the car of [Mark]

c. [Mark’s] car (Abney (1987: 270))

On the contrary, pronouns are typical determiners:

1. pronouns do not occur with modifiers typical for NPs

(25) a. *Mark’s [you]

b. Mark’s [car] (Abney (1987: 281))

background image

24

2. pronouns can appear with nouns within the so called idiosyncratic gaps, e.g.

(26) a. I Claudius

b. You fool

(Abney (1987: 282))

1.3 Further remarks on the structure of nominal phrases

Placing Determiners in the position of the head of a nominal phrase solves the main

problems that were left untouched by the traditional analysis of nominals. However,

there still remain queries left without answers, e.g. the question of the position of

elements intervening between Determiners and Nouns (written in italics) in (27) below.

(27) a. the many good man

(Abney (1987:290))

b. Ø two parts steel

c. Ø two dozen roses

d. Ø three men

(Abney (1987: 291))

The phrases presented above are the instances of a quantifier phrase - (27a), a

measure phrase - (27b), a semi-numeral phrase - (27c) and a numeral phrase - (27d).

They are all understood by Jackendoff (1977) as instances of treble-bar NPs, which are

unacceptable in the X-bar Theory. Abney’s (1987) answer to this problem is

proclaiming the existence of an additional projection appearing between a DP and an

NP, i.e. an AP (Adjective Phrase). Both structures - Jackendoff’s (28a) and Abney’s

(28b) - are shown below:

background image

25

(28) a. N’’’

(Jackendoff (1977: 291))

b. DP

(Abney (1987:336))


Possr/D N’’

D AP


QP/NP

N’

DegP A’


two parts

two

N

A

NP

steel

parts

N
steel

In comparison with Jackendoff’s proposal in (28a), the structure offered by Abney in

(28b) shows the compliance with the X-bar Theory - no treble-bar projections are

involved. What is more, it provides us with a full structure with a place for an Adjective

Phrase.

Abney assumes that Quantifiers, Adverbs and descriptive Adjectives belong to a

single category of Adjectives (Abney (1987:293)) and that pre-nominal and post-

nominal Adjective Phrases differ in their inner structure and nature (Abney (1987:326)).

The first assumption stems from the following facts:

1. Quantifiers and Adjectives differ mostly in their semantics; the differences in

supporting the partitive constructions and functioning as pronouns do not

concern the comparative and superlative (Abney (1987:301)).

2. Adverbs and Adjectives take the same degree words and Adverbs as their

modifiers as shown in (29) (Abney (1987:301)). The ending -ly present with

Adverbs is just a prepositional adjective Case-marker and may be treated like

verbal ending -ing (Abney (1987:302) after Larson (1987)).

(29) a. sufficiently quick

b. sufficiently quickly

(Abney (1987: 301))

background image

26

3. All Adjectives, Adverbs and Quantifiers share common [+N] feature (Abney

(1987:302)).

Therefore, adjective phrases, quantifier phrases and adverb phrases are identical

in their internal structure.

However, as has already been mentioned, there is a difference between pre-

nominal and post-nominal adjective phrases. According to Abney (1987), pre-nominal

adjective phrases are APs taking an NP as their complement, whereas post-nominal

adjective phrases are in truth Degree Phrases (DegPs).

As can be seen in (30) below, degree words within adjective phrases, e.g. too,

behave similarly to Determiners within nominal expressions. They modify all kinds of

adjective phrases appearing in the initial position, as in (30a) and (30b), and they cannot

be multiplied, as shown in (30c)

(30) a. too many

as hungrily
so long

b. too sick

as happy


c. *as too sick

*too as happy

Therefore, it is natural to claim that Degree words project DegPs and take

adjective phrases as complements, just like Determiners project DPs and take nominal

phrases as therir complements (Abney (1987: 298)). The structure of the DegP with

proper examples is presented by means of a P-maker in (31) below:

background image

27

(31)

DegP

.

DegP

Deg’

Ø

AP

Deg AP

much [+Q]

too

tall

quite [+Adj] as nice

(Abney (1987:306))

As can be seen in (31), Abney’s proposal covers even adjective phrases which

function as modifiers of phrases like too tall that have already been recognized as

DegPs.

The case of pre-nominal adjective phrases is much different. First of all, pre-

nominal adjective phrases cannot take typical PP complements, whereas post nominal

DegPs must have complements, e.g.:

(32) a. the [proud] man

*the [proud of his son] man

b. *the man [proud]

the man [proud of his son]

(Abney (1987:326))

This query can be explained if we assume that instead of a typical PP the pre-

nominal AP takes an NP as its complement. At the same time, it appears that Adjectives

have similar properties to auxiliary verbs within verbal phrases, i.e. appearing as

‘auxiliaries’ they cannot take complements characteristic for their class and they f-select

NPs. Therefore, it is possible to claim that Adjectives are ‘defective’ Nouns, just as

corresponding Auxiliaries are defective Verbs (Abney (1987: 327)). This leads us to the

conclusion that the only structure possible for pre-nominal adjective phrases is the

structure presented in (28b).

background image

28

Conclusion

In this chapter it has been shown that the classical GB structure of nominal phrases,

which treats them as NPs headed by a Noun with a Determiner in the [Spec; NP]

position is inadequate. In the case of Determiners, the GB analysis violates the

constraints of the X-bar theory. What is more, it fails to provide an appropriate

explanation for the cross-linguistic phenomenon of multiple determiners found in

languages of Romance and Slavic groups. In comparison with the structure of CPs, the

GB analysis of NPs ignores the similarities between Determiners and Complementisers,

which suggest that the former may fulfil the same function of introducing the

descriptive content of the phrase. In addition to this, the classical structure does not

explain the difference in understanding the s-projection of clauses and nominal phrases.

Abney’s (1987) proposal of analysing nominal phrases as DPs removes the

deficiencies of the former representation. It also accounts for the phenomena such as:

the argument structure of Poss-ing gerundive constructions, the strong agreement within

the nominal phrase, corresponding to the Inflection in clauses and post-nominal

adjectives in English. The explanation is offered also for the question concerning the

position of adjectives, quantifiers and other elements intervening between a Determiner

and a Noun, which according to Abney project their own projections (DegPs and APs).

background image

29

Chapter 2

Functional projections within the DP

Introduction

In the first chapter, following Abney (1987), the existence of the Determiner Phrase has

been postulated as a functional projection built upon the Nominal Phrase. A nominal

phrase is headed by a functional element - D, just as a clause is headed by a functional

element I. However, aspiring to a uniformity between nominal and verbal structures,

motivated by the equal importance of both elements for the meaning of a sentence, we

are obliged to analyse the possibility of other functional projections existing within the

DP-projections intervening between the Determiner and its complement – NP, parallel

to projections appearing between an IP and an NP.

Chapter 2 discusses numerous proposals of functional projections appearing

within the DP. Sections 2.1 to 2.3 present an Agreement Phrase (AgrP), a Number

Phrase (NP) and a Quantifier Phrase (QP). Section 2.4 is concerned with the order of

adjectives within a nominal phrase from Cinque’s (1994) and Scott’s (2002)

perspective. Section 2.5 introduces the proposal of nP (a little n). In section 2.6 a

Demonstrative Phrase (DemP) and a Possessive Phrase (PossP) are discussed. Finally,

section 2.6 provides a discussion of the hierarchy of elements appearing within a DP.

background image

30

2.1 AgrP - Agreement Phrase

The issue of agreement between various elements appearing within a DP was

raised by Abney (1987) and introduced as one of the cross-linguistic facts proving the

similarity of verbal and nominal phrases. Agreement is understood to be a feature

carried by the head of the phrase - D (cf. Chapter 1 (13)). It is manifested by proper

forms of nouns and neighbouring elements showing the same number, person or case.

On the basis of Hungarian data, Szabolcsi (1994) postulates the existence of Agreement

as a whole projection intervening between NP and DP. The data demonstrating this

problem are shown in (1).

(1) a. az en kalap-om

the I hat-1

st

sing.

‘my hat’

b. a te kalap-od
the you hat- 2

nd

sing.

‘your hat’


c. a Peter kalap-ja
the Peter- NOM hat-3

rd

sing.

‘Peter’s hat’

As can be seen in (1), Hungarian possessors are marked with nominative case

and show agreement with the noun that follows them. This structure is an exact

reflection of the relation between a subject and a verb within a sentence. What is more,

Hungarian possessors may also occupy frontal position within the nominal phrase,

preceding the article and the noun, as in (2b).

(2) a. a Mari kalap-ja

the Mari- NOM hat-3

rd

sing.

‘Mary’s hat’


background image

31

b. Mari-nak a kalap-ja
Mari- DAT the hat- 3

rd

sing.

‘Mary’s hat’

Szabolcsi (1994) claims that (2b) is derived from (2a). The possessor Mari

occupying the position of [Spec; AgrP] moves leftwards to the [Spec; DP] where it is

assigned the dative case. The structure introduced by Szabolcsi is as follows (cf. (1a-c)

and (2a-b)):

(3) DP

Spec

D’

D

AgrP

Spec Agr’

Agr

NP

az

en

-om

kalap

a

te

-od

kalap

a

Peter -ja

kalap

a

Mari -ja

kalap

Mari- nak

i

a

t

i

-ja

kalap

Another piece of evidence in favour of the AgrP is based on the comparative

analysis of the position of particular adjectives in Romance and Germanic languages

and parametrised N-to-Agr movement postulated by Cinque (1994). By comparing

English and Italian data, it can be seen that some adjectives appearing prenominally in

English follow the noun in Italian (cf. (4 a-b)).

(4) a. the beautifu big red ball

[English]

b. la bella grande palla rossa

[Italian]

the beautiful big ball red

(Cinque (1994;93))

background image

32

The classical GB analysis of Adjective Phrases assumes that they are attached to

the nominal phrase by adjunction. Due to the fact that they are neither complements nor

specifiers of the Noun Phrase they can recursively occur in the position intervening

between nouns and determiners and therefore create the structure presented in (5)

below.

(5) N’’

Spec N’

AP N’

AP

N’

AP

N’

N

(Radford (1988: 201))

However, the structure in (5) does not account for the data in (4) – it is actually

just the opposite: it creates a conceptually unsatisfactory result of allowing left-

adjunction in Germanic languages but right-adjunction in Romance. The structural

difference between the data in (4a-b) can be explained in two ways: either by claiming

that the final adjective in Romance languages is lowered into the position below the

noun, or proposing the leftward movement of a noun from the N position into some

empty head position intervening between the two APs.

Cinque (1994) supports the thesis of leftward noun movement. The piece of

evidence he produces is based on similar verb movement present in both language

background image

33

groups (i.e. the obligatory raising of a finite V). As a result, the following structure is

postulated:

(6) DP

Spec D’

D AgrP

Spec Agr’

AP

Agr AgrP

Spec Agr’

AP

Agr AgrP

Spec Agr’

AP

Agr NP

N’

N

a.

the beautiful

big red ball

b.

la bella

grande palla

i

rossa

t

i

As can be seen in (6), Cinque rejects the classical GB interpretation of adjectives

treated as adjuncts of the NP, adjoined to the N’ and expanding it into another N’, and

places them in the position of [Spec;AgrP]. This leaves us with empty Agr head

positions within each AgrP, constituting possible landing sites for head-to-head

movement. At the same time, the conceptually unsatisfactory difference between left-

background image

34

and right-adjunction ceases to exist. Therefore, the noun – adjective order within a DP

may differ across languages.

2.2 NumP- Number Phrase

On the basis of data from Celtic and Semitic languages the notion of Number

Phrase has been developed (Ritter (1988, 1991), Duffield (1995), Mohammad (1988),

Lyons (1997), among others). The elements of nominal phrases in these languages show

strong agreement with respect to number and gender. Therefore, although all the lexical

elements originate within the NP, they are moved higher to be assigned case (the head

noun) or to gain the proper number and gender (modifying elements – possessors)

(Ritter (1991)).

The structure proposed by Duffield (1995), after Ritter (1991) and others, with

proper examples is presented in (7) below:

background image

35

(7) DP

Spec D’

D AgrP

Spec Agr’

Agr NumP

Spec Num’

Num NP

AP NP

Spec

N

a. sieq

i

Willy

j

t

i

t

i

l-leminija t

j

t

i

b. guth

i

t

i

t

i

aidir an tsagairt t

i

c. an leabhar

i

nua

t

i



a. sieq Willy l-leminija

[Hebrew]

foot-fem. sing. Willy the-right-fem. sing.

‘Willy’s right foot’

b. guth aidir an tsagairt

[Irish]

voice strong the priest-GEN
‘the priest’s powerful voice’

c. an leabhar nua

[Irish]

the book new
‘the new book’ (Duffield (1995: 309)

Assuming that the core position of all elements within a phrase is universal for

all languages, the same structure should appear in Celtic and in Semitic languages.

background image

36

Therefore, the basic position of both the modifying adjective phrase and the possessor is

on the left-hand side of the Noun. The possessor, later on, moves to its target site from

the A’-position in [Spec;NP] to the [Spec;AgrP]. The functional projection of Number

caries the features of number and gender, and provides the landing site for the Noun.

The head noun is said to move from the N position to the functional position of Num

which accounts for the leftward position of the head noun in relation to the possessor

and modifying adjective phrases. In Irish, the Noun undergoes head-to-head movement

either to Num or to D if the latter is not occupied by some other element (cf. (7b) and

(7c)).

The NumP is one of the first functional projections claimed to appear between a

DP and an NP. However, there is no proof for its existence in Germanic and Slavic

languages. Therefore it will not be mentioned in Chapter 3, devoted to the structure of

Polish nominals.

2.3. QP - Quantifier Phrase

Apart from articles, possessors and demonstratives, another important group of

modifiers are quantifiers (e.g. some, many, all, (a) little, (a) few etc.). Although they are

in the complementary distribution with articles, they are recognized as a different class

requiring their own projection within the nominal phrase – a Quantifier Phrase.

However, the position of the Quantifier Phrase is not explicit. Following Giusti (1991,

1997), we must consider the existence of three different groups of quantifiers appearing

in different positions: quantifiers which must precede an article, as in (8), quantifiers

background image

37

that may follow an article, as in (9), and quantifiers that do not co-occur with articles, as

in (10):


(8) a. tutti *(i) ragazzi
‘all the children’
b. *i tutti ragazzi
c. li ho visti tutti
‘I saw them all’

(9) a. molti Ø *i ragazzi
‘many boys’
b. i molti ragazzi

‘the many boys’

c. ne ho visti molti/ *ne ho visti i molti

‘I saw many of them’


(10) a. alcuni/ *i ragazzi

‘some boys’

b. ne ho visti alcuni .

‘I saw some of them’

(Giusti (1997: 114))


The quantifiers like molti ‘many’ behave like adjectives. They follow the article

and, when placed in the phrase initial position, they cause the expression to become

ungrammatical (cf. (9a) and (9b)). At the same time, they show agreement with regard

to umber and gender with the head noun. Therefore, it is possible to claim that, in fact,

they belong to the same lexical class as common adjectives. Consequently, just as

adjectives, they appear in a DP internal position of the high [Spec; AgrP], as shown in

(11) below.

background image

38

(11) DP

D

AgrP

Spec Agr’

Agr

NP

Spec N’

AP

N

i due ragazzi simpatici t

i

the

two boys nice

(Giusti (1997: 115))

A piece of evidence supporting this theory is to be found in Romanian

encliticised definite article (Giusti (1991)). In Romanian, the definite article

encliticcises on the leftmost element of the nominal phrase: a noun or an adjective

moved into the D position. The same rule applies in the case of quantifiers and,

therefore, it is possible to claim that they do function as adjectives. As shown in (12) the

quantifier ambi ‘both,’ as well as the adjective frumosi ‘nice,' carries the encliticcsed

article.

(12) a. ambii baieti

both-the children

b. frumosii baieti

nice-the children

(Giusti (1994: 120))

background image

39

However, according to Giusti (1991, 1994, 1997) not all quantifiers have the

same properties. The quantifiers as tutti 'all’ display selectional properties over the DP

they are followed by. They require the nominal phrase to be definite, therefore they are

followed by the article + noun construction as has been shown in (8a-b). The

explanation for this phenomenon proposed by Giusti (1991) is as follows: quantifiers

that are followed by articles are in fact external to DP and create their own projection

above the whole DP as shown in (13) below (cf. (8a)):

(13) QP

Spec Q’

Q DP

tutti

i ragazzi

all

the boys

(Giusti (1997. 114))

This analysis is repeated by Giusti and Leko (1995) in the context of pronominal

DPs modified by the quantifier tutti ‘all’ in Italian and its equivalents in French and

English. Comparing the data in (14a-c), with typical constructions of tutti + nominal

DP, as, for instance, in (8) and (13), they propose the structure shown in (15).

(14) a. voi/ noi tutti

[Italian]

b. nous/ vous tous

[French]

c. you/ we all

[English]

background image

40

(15) QP

Spec Q’

Q DP

voi/noi

i

tutti

t

i

vous/nous

i

tous

t

i

you/we

i

all

t

i

According to Giusti and Leko (1995), pronouns originate within the DP and are

moved upwards to the [Spec; QP] position, as opposed to typical nominal DPs shown in

(13), which stay in the lower parts of the phrase. This claim, however, is highly

questionable. There seems to be no reason for the pronoun rising (this is not

syntactically motivated). What is more, Polish data discussed by Rutkowski (2002c)

constitute a clear set of counterarguments. The Polish equivalent of the quantifier tutti-

wszyscy, which behaves exactly like regular adjectives, shows strong agreement in

terms of case, number and gender with the head noun, as well as with the pronoun (cf.

(16)).

(16)

a. [wszyscy lingwiści] czytali mój artykuł

all linguists read my article
‘all linguists read my article’

b. [wy wszyscy] czytaliście mój artykuł

you all

read

my article

‘you all read my article’

c. *[wszyscy wy] czytaliście mój artykuł

all

you read

my article

(Rutkowski (2002c:163))

background image

41

On the basis of data in (16), Rutkowski (2001, 2002a, 2002c) claims that both

the quantifier and pronoun are DP internal. The quantifier wszyscy is placed in the head

Q position and takes a complement, i.e. NP. The pronoun originates within the NP and

it is moved to the D position as a result of the N-to-D raising of pronouns. This leads to

the uniformity of the basic structure of Quantifier Phrase and neutralises the artificial

division of quantifiers. Rutkowski’s proposal is represented in the P-maker below.

(17) DP

Spec D’


D

QP

Spec

Q’

Q NP

GEN (Q)

wy-Gen

i

wszyscy

t

i

(Rutkowski (2007b:88))

However, the structure given by Rutkowski (2007b) is quite problematic.

According to the Head Movement Constraint, the element moved passes through each

head position intervening between the original and target positions. Here, the pronoun

wy skips an intervening Q, which is already occupied by wszyscy.

background image

42

2.4 The order of adjectives

According to Abney (1987) (cf. Chapter 1, 1.3), adjectives constitute two separate

groups: pre-nominal adjectives, which form their own functional projection appearing in

the position intervening between a DP and an NP, and post-nominal adjectives, which

appear within Degree Phrases bellow the NP. What is more, adjectives are said to be

‘defective’ Nouns and fulfil similar functions within a DP as Auxiliaries within a CP.

However, there are some inconsistencies in Abney’s analysis of adjectives and

other components of the DP Hypothesis. According to Abney, Auxiliaries and

Determiners, being functional elements, are members of a closed class. They do not

contribute significantly to the meaning of the clause and are inseparable from the lexical

element they introduce. Adjectives, though claimed to be functional elements too, do

not match this description – they are members of an open lexical class, they can be

separated from the noun, and they do contribute to the meaning. At the same time, the

existence of post-nominal adjectives (the trigger for Abney’s interpretation) constitutes

the basis for Cinque’s (1994) analysis of Agreement Phrase (cf. Chapter 2, 2.1), which

postulates that APs occurring within a DP occupy the position of [Spec;AgrP] (cf. (6)).

Another query that stays unsolved under Abney’s analysis is the order of

Adjectives. In most languages elements modifying nouns have a strict and highly

restricted order of appearance. Each adjective appearing within a DP must be placed in

a proper position according to the semantic group it belongs to. According to the

research conducted by Pereltsvaig (2007), only 11.5% of native speakers of Russian do

not follow the universal order of adjectives. In this case Cinque’s (1994) analysis of

APs seems to be more justified. According to him, Adjective Phrases placed within

functional projections undergo selection under the conditions placed by the functional

background image

43

head. Therefore, it is claimed that each Agreement Phrase hosting an AP within it

carries one of the attributive features, the order of which is as follows:

(18) possessor> cardinal> ordinal> quality> size> shape> colour> nationality

(Cinque (1994: 96))

The model presented by Cinque has undergone numerous modifications and

reshapings. New projections have been postulated and the analysis became more

detailed and specific. Scott’s (2002) analysis constitutes a good example of such

modification. According to Scott (2002), the number of AP-related functional

projections within a DP in much bigger than the eight introduced by Cinque (1994). The

universal hierarchy of DP elements proposed by him is as follows:

(19) Det> ordinal number> cardinal number> subjective comment> evidential>

size> length> height> speed> depth> width> weight> temperature> wetness>
age> shape> colour> nationality/origin> material> compound element> NP

(Scott (2002;114))

The application of the model is presented in (20) below.

background image

44

(20) DP

D

D’

AdvP Subj. CommentP

AP

Subj. CommentP’

e

SizeP

e LengthP

AP LengthP’

(Scott (2002:106))

e ColourP

AP Colour P’

e

NP

What is more, Scott (2002) introduces the notion of Focus Phrase appearing

within the DP as an instance of another functional projection – the landing site for

elements undergoing preposing, i.e. the movement of the emphasised element towards

the left side of the phrase. The emphatic use of preposing in English is not uncommon.

The process can be applied even for more than one constituent. The emphasised

elements are moved to the [Spec;FocP] position, appearing below the DP, as shown in

(21).

(21) a. It’s [

DP

the green

i

big t

i

chair] that I want.

b. It’s [

DP

the old

j

green

i

big t

j

t

i

chair] that I want.

c. It’s [

DP

the nice green

i

big t

i

chair] that I want.

d. It’s [

DP

the nice green

i

old

j

big t

j

t

i

chair] that I want.

e.

[

DP

Carol’s horrible

i

six t

i

children] made life miserable for her second husband.

(Scott (2002: 113))

really

that

cool

long

red

dress

background image

45

f.

DP

D’

D FocP

AP

FocP’

e

SizeP

AP ColourP

AP ColourP’

e

NP

All the proposals made by both Cinque (1994) and Scott (2002) are based

on the assumption that the order of adjectives within a nominal expression is

syntactically motivated and the influence of the speaker’s interpretation ends where the

preposing starts (Rutkowski (2007b)). Therefore, it is possible to assume that both

structures are universal. However, a more complex structure introduced by Scott (2002)

precisely exhausts the subject.

2.5 Little n - the nominal shells

One of the most awkward syntactic questions concerns the structure of constructions

with a ditransitive verb. According to the basic GB-theory assumptions, there could be

only one complement within a phrase and, due to this fact, the idea of the indirect object

being an additional complement is unacceptable. The analysis developed by Larson

(1988) and updated by Chomsky (1995a) casts light on this case. The analysis is as

the

green

i

big

t

i

chair

background image

46

follows: a verbal phrase consists of two verbal projections – shells; the lower shell is the

projection of a lexical verb, whereas the higher one is the projection of a light verb - v,

which is given a null spell-out and whose meaning is closely connected with the

meaning of its complement. At the beginning, the lexical verb is merged between the

two objects, then it is adjoined to the light verb – v, which is strongly affixal in nature

and triggers the Move operation. An example structure is given in (22) below.

(22) a. Mary gave a book to John.

b. vP

Mary v

v

0

VP

gave v

0

[

DP

a book] V’

V [

PP

to John]

gave

(Hornstein et al. (2005: 99))

The structure in (22) remains in agreement with The Uniformity of Theta

Assignment Hypothesis (UTAH) (Baker (1988, 1997)), which requires linking specific

theta-roles to particular positions in initial syntactic structure. And therefore the Theme

theta-role must be assigned to a book in the object position, the Goal theta-role to John,

and the Agent role must be assigned to Mary in the subject position.

Assuming that the structure of nominal expressions is similar or even identical

with the structure of verbal expressions, the existence of little n within the DP has been

proposed (cf.Valois (1996), Bhattacharya (1998), and many others). The little n selects

background image

47

an NP and introduces an Agent. The surface order, again, appears to be the result of

Move operation (Adger (2003)). An example structure is presented below:

(23) a. Richard’s gift of the helicopter to the hospital

b. DP

Richard’s D’

D nP

Richard

n’

n

0

NP

gift

n

0

of the helicopter N’

gift to the hospital

(Adger (2003: 268))

The motivation for the existence of the little n is the case checking of the

nominal elements within the DP. D checks the Genitive case of the Agent and having a

strong [gen] feature causes the movement of the Agent from the [Spec;nP] position in

order to satisfy the locality requirement. The little n carries the weak [of] feature and,

due to this, it checks the case of the of-Phrase but does not cause movement (Adger

(2003)).

A more recent interpretation of this structure is presented by Radford (2004).

According to him, a lexical noun gift merges with its internal arguments: a Goal to the

hospital and a Theme of the helicopter. Then the NP merges with a little n, whose

specifier corresponds to the Agent phrase Richard. The little n is strongly affixal in

nature and therefore triggers the movement of the Noun. The whole nP merges with a

background image

48

DP headed by a null Determiner. The null Determiner is able to assign the Genitive

case to the nominal Richard. The null D carries the [EPP] feature requiring it to be

extended into a DP projection with a proper specifier. As a result it triggers the

movement of the Richard to the [Spec; DP] position.

2.6 DemP – Demonstrative Phrase and PossP - Possessive Phrase

According to Abney (1987), articles, demonstratives and possessives occupy the same

syntactic position, i.e. a D position. This assumption is confirmed by the fact that those

elements in English are in complementary distribution. However, it is inconsistent with

the data taken from other Germanic, Romance and Slavic languages.


(24)

a. ta moja książka

[Polish]

this my book

‘this book of mine’


b. diese unserve wunderbaren Bücher

[German]

these our wonderful books

‘these wonderful books of ours’

(Rutkowski (2007b: 257-258))

As shown in (24) above, in some languages both possessive and demonstrative

pronouns can appear within one nominal phrase. Taking into consideration the data in

(24) it is no longer possible to claim that possessives and demonstratives occupy the

same position within the syntactic structure. What is more, they show agreement with

the Noun they modify, therefore, they are similar in syntactic behaviour rather to lexical

not to functional elements (Zlatić (1997)). In traditional perspective, Agreement is said

to involve a c-command relation between a modifier and an element modified, i.e. they

background image

49

must fill a specifier and a head positions. To account for the presence of overt

agreement in the data in (24), it is possible to claim that both pronominal elements

occupy [Spec; XP] position. Due to the fact that a demonstrative pronoun usually

appears phrase-initially, Lecko (1999) suggests that it occupies [Spec, DP] position.

Then, a possessive pronoun must be placed in different Spec position. According to

Veselovská (1995), it appears within a Possessive Phrase, placed closely below a DP

projection. The structure steaming from the analysis presented above is shown in (25):

(25)

(Rutkowski (2007b:258))

According to Giusti (1997), the structure given in (25) above illustrates only the

final word order, which is a result of movements appearing during the derivation. This

is confirmed on the basis of data taken from Spanish presented in (26) below:

POSSESSIVE

PRONOUN

DEMONSTRATIVE
PRONOUN

NOUN

background image

50

(26) a. este

libro

this- masc. sing book

‘this book’


b. el libro este

the book this-masc. sing.

‘this book’

c. *el este libro

the this-masc.sing. book

‘this book’

d. *este el libro

this-masc. sing. the book

‘this book’

(Rutkowski (2007b: 259-261))

As shown in (26), the demonstrative pronoun este may precede, as well as,

follow the noun. Giusti (1997) claims that a Demonstrative- Noun order presented in

(26a) is a result of a movent of the Noun. The overt agreement between the Noun and

the modifier may apply only if they are in a c-command relation, therefore it is not

possible to claim that a demonstrative originates lower in the structure than a Noun. As

far as the position of the Demonstrative is concerned, it can be neither a [Spec; DP] nor

a D position. The D position is already occupied by a definite article el (cf. (26 b-d)),

whilst the construction with a Demonstrative in [Spec; DP] position is ungrammatical

(cf. (26d)). Therefore, it is possible to claim that a demonstrative pronoun occupies a

specifier position within a Demonstrative Phrase (DemP) - a functional projection

appearing between a DP and an NP. From there it may be moved upward to [Spec; DP]

in order to satisfy the requirements connected with D

0

(Rutkowski (2007b)).

On the basis of the analysis presented above the initial position of possessive

pronouns may be established. In Spanish both demonstrative and possessive pronouns

may appear within one nominal phrase as shown in (27) below:

background image

51

(27) el cuadro

i

redondo este suyo t

i

the picture round this his
‘this found picture of his’

(Rutkowski ( 2007b: 262))

According to Giusti (2002), the final syntax of el cuadro redondo este syuo is a

result of a movement of the Noun cuadro. The rest of the elements stay in their initial

positions. Therefore the possessive pronoun is claimed to appear within a projection

situated closely above the NP but lower than a DemP. Grohmann and Panagiotidis

(2004) suggest that [Spec; nP] should be accepted as the initial position of possessive

pronouns.

2.7 The hierarchy of functional elements within the DP

The issue closing this chapter pertains to the order of functional elements within the DP.

The result of my analysis will be the structure of nominal phrase which I will adopt in

this thesis

As has been shown in section 2.5, gift of the helicopter to the hospital is an nP.

Analysing examples given in (28) below, it is possible to establish the position of the nP

within the structure of DP:

(28) a. Richard’s [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital]

(Adger (2003: 268))

b. my [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital]

c. my generous [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital]

d. Richard’s generous [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital]

e. some generous [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital]

f. *Richard’s [

nP

gift generous of the helicopter to the hospital]

g. *Richard’s [

nP

gift of the helicopter generous to the hospital]

h. *Richard’s [

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital] generous

i. *[

nP

gift of the helicopter to the hospital] some generous

background image

52

As can be seen in (28 a-i), the little n stays lowest within the structure of the DP.

It is preceded by all the other elements, i.e. determiners, possessives, adjectives and

quantifiers. What is more, other functional elements of the DP intervening within the nP

cause the ungrammaticality of the phrase (cf. (28g-h)). On the basis of (28c-d), it may

be concluded that elements appearing under D, Possessives and Quantifiers, precede

APs. Therefore, bearing in mind the stipulations made in the previous sections of this

chapter, a claim could be made that the hierarchy of functional elements is as follows:


(29) DP

my D’

D PossP

my Poss’

Poss QP


Spec Q’

Q AgrP

generous Agr’

Agr nP

Spec n

n

0

NP

gift

n

0

of the helicopter N’

gift to the hospital

However, there is still one functional projection already discussed but not included

within the structure above – i.e. the Number Phrase. According to Megerdoomian

background image

53

(2008), the position of NumP is between the two nominal shells: the nP and the NP.

Following Travis (1992), Megerdoomian claims that Num carries the information about

the cardinality of the nominal phrase, and when projected, it gives the +SAQ (specified

quantity) interpretation to the noun phrase. This is necessary because this is the way in

which nominals, all marked as mass within the Lexicon, gain the count interpretation

(Megerdoomian (2008: 88) after Borer (2001)).

On balance, the structure of DP that I will adopt for the subsequent part of my

analysis of the nominal constructions is the structure consisting of all the projections

mentioned in this chapter and arranged in the following order of appearance:

(30)

DP> PossP> QP> AgrP

1

>…> AgrP

n

> nP> NumP> NP

I assume that the number of AgrPs appearing within the DP is not limited and that it

depends on the actual need, therefore in (30) AgrPs are provided with index numbers.

The index n expresses the theoretical lack of limit on the number of AgrPs within the

DP. The P-maker illustrating the structure is presented in (31) below:

background image

54

(31)DP

D’

D PossP

Poss’

Poss QP

Spec Q’

Q AgrP

Spec Agr’

Agr nP

Spec n

n

0

NumP


Spec Num’



Num NP


The Focus Phrase discussed in section 2.4 (cf. (21 f)) is not included within the

structure presented in (31). This is motivated by the fact that the presence of this

projection is necessary only in case of emphatic preposing which I will not discuss. The

lack of FocP does not disturb the order of projections, and it will not influence the

analysis that follows.

background image

55

Conclusion

In Chapter 2, I have presented the structure of the DP has been presented, following the

recent analyses available in the literature. One by one, the functional projections

appearing within the nominal phrases: Possessor Phrase, Quantifier Phrase, Agreement

Phrases hosting Adjectives, little n and Number Phrase have been overviewed. Their

place within the nominal structure has been discussed and the reasons for postulating

the existence of each of them have been highlighted.

The Possessor Phrase is the first projection appearing bellow the DP, it hosts the

possessors. The PossP cannot appear in the same position as Saxon genitives - this is a

restriction steming from the UTAH. The second in the order of appearance is the

projection of Quantifiers. According to the theory of the Genitive of Quantification, the

QP is placed within the DP, even though it used to be claimed to be nominal-external.

Following the QP are the Agreement Phrases hosting Adjectives, whose order is

restricted and must follow the universal hierarchy. The number of possible AgrPs within

the DP is not restricted and depends on the need.

Below the AgrP complex, there appears the double layer of nominal shells: nP

and NP. The existence of nP has been proclaimed on the basis of the following three

assumptions:

4. the structure of nominal phrases should be as close to the structure of Verbal

phrases as possible.

5. the requirements of case checking within the nominal expression (especially

the locality condition not satisfied if Agent is claimed to Merge straight in

[Spec;DP] position)

background image

56

6. the UTAH - the requirement linking specific theta-roles to particular

positions in initial syntactic structure.

The lowest projection within the DP is the NP - the projection of a lexical head -

a Noun, which can take complements, as has been assumed from the very beginning of

the research into the structure of nominal phrases.

background image

57

Chapter 3

The DP in Polish

Introduction

Polish is a member of the group of languages which demonstrate no overt instantiation

of the functional element D. Therefore, it is not unexpectable to come across an analysis

of nominal phrases in Polish which assumes that there is no DP projection in this

language. However, the case of Polish is not an isolated one. The same feature may be

observed, among many others, in Chinese, Japanese and in other languages belonging to

the Slavic family. On the theoretical level of research pertaining to this topic, two major

ways of reasoning can be seen:

1. One presenting nominal phrases in languages mentioned strictly as NPs

without the DP layer, and therefore, explaining the syntactic difference

between languages with and without Determiners (Fukui (1986), Zlatić

(1997), Chierchia (1998), Willim (2000), Kim (2004), Bošković (2003,

2004, 2005, 2008) among others);

2. One adopting the idea of functional projection appearing above the NP

without an element, which could appear under D, at the same time being in

favour of universality of the syntactic structure (Corver (1992), Longobardi

(1994), Progovac (1998), Yadroff (1999), Migdalski (2000), Sio (2006),

Perltsvaig (2007), Rutkowski (2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2002c, 2007a, 2007b,

2009) among others).

In this chapter I will present both approaches to the DP, although, I am in

favour of the analysis positing the existence of DP in Polish. I will start by outlining the

background image

58

arguments both for and against the NP interpretation of nominals (section 3.1). Later, I

will move towards the second interpretation, focusing mostly on the argumentation and

analysis as presented by Rutkowski (2007b) in his PhD dissertation. Finally, in section

I will concentrate on the structure, with the use of which Polish nominal phrases could

be described.

3.1 Is there a DP in Polish?

The existence of languages having in their lexicon no element that could function as an

article is not infrequently the major argument against proclaiming Abney’s DP

Hypothesis as universal (cf., for instance, Fukui (1986)). This observation makes

nominals be treated as they are understood under classical GB analysis – as NPs.

Consequently, the element D is still placed under the [Spec; NP] position and adjectives

are treated as adjuncts. The structure is shown in the P-maker in (1) below:

(1) NP

D

N’

AP N’

N

The same structure is applicable to Polish. It is supposed to explain phenomena

such as the Left Branch Extraction (LBE) or the impossibility of a nominal construction

background image

59

with the double genitive (Bošković (2005, 2008)). Both phenomena are discussed in

detail in the following subsections of this chapter.

3.1.1 Left Branch Extraction (LBF)

The Left Branch Extraction is a key argument against applying the DP Hypothesis to

languages without a lexical instantiation of the functional Determiner. Bošković (2005,

2008) illustrates this on the basis of examples from Serbo-Croatian and Latin, shown

below:

(2) Serbo-Croatian:

a. Cijegi si vidio [t

i

oca]?

whose AUX-2

nd

sing. seen father

‘Whose father did you see?’

b. Tai je vidio [t

i

kola].

that AUX-3

rd

sing. seen car

‘That car, he saw.’

c. Lijepei je vidio [t

i

kuce].

beautiful AUX-3

rd

sing. seen houses

‘Beautiful houses, he saw.’

d. Kolikoi je zaradila [t

i

novca]?

how-much AUX-3

rd

sing. earned money

‘How much money did she earn?’

(3) Latin:

a. Cuiami amat Cicero [t

i

puellam]?

whose loves Cicero girl
‘Whose girl does Cicero love?’

b. Qualesi Cicero amat [t

i

puellas]?

what-kind-of Cicero loves girls
‘What kind of girls does Cicero love?’

(Bošković (2005: 2-3))

background image

60

As can be seen in the examples above, pre-nominal modifiers in Serbo-Croatian

and in Latin can be extracted from within the nominal group. Their landing site is the

initial position on the left-hand side of the sentence (Bošković (2005)). The LBE is

characteristic for articleless languages only and, in languages like English, it is simply

ungrammatical (Uriagereka (1988), Bošković (2005, 2008)). According to Bošković

(2005, 2008), the difference between the two groups of languages lies in the fact that

languages with articles have a DP projection, whereas articleless languages have only

an NP projection - the traditional NP. What is more, they differ in the position of

Adjectives. In DP-languages, as suggested by Abney (1987) (cf. Chapter 1, section 1.3),

Adjectives are heads of a functional projection appearing between a DP and an NP,

therefore, they alone do not form a full constituent and cannot be extracted – as being a

full constituent is a condition for extraction. In non-DP-languages, on the other hand,

Adjectives are adjuncts, therefore they form constituents and are prone to extraction

(Bošković (2005)). The graphical representation of nominal phrases and the LBE in

both languages is shown in (4) and (5) below:

(4) LBE in DP-languages

(Rutkowski (2007b; 56))

background image

61

(5) LBE in non-DP-languages:

(Rutkowski (2007b;56))

According to the Minimalist theory, it is possible to claim that in the case of the

LBE discontinuous or scattered spellout occurs (Fanselow and Ćavar (2002)).

According to Chomsky (1995a, 2000), each movement takes place in two stages:

Copying and Deletion (the copy theory of movement). Firstly, the element which

undergoes movement is copied and merged in the target position. Later, the original

copy is deleted, i.e. is given a null spellout. As Fanselow and Ćavar (2002) suggest, in

the case of the LBE, the null spellout can be applied only to the part of the constituent

undergoing movement. Then, not the whole original element is removed, but a part of

each copy undergoes deletion, as shown in the example below:

(6)

a. [Którą książkę] chcesz przeczytać [którą książkę]?

b. [Którą książkę] chcesz przeczytać [którą książkę]? (Rutkowski (2007b:58))

background image

62

As can be seen in (6a) the movement of the wh-phrase którą książkę is the effect

of copying of the whole wh-phrase, merging it in the sentence-initial position and,

finally, deleting the entire lower copy. (6a) and (6b) do not differ in the application of

wh-movement, however, in the case of sentence in (6b) after copying and merging,

discontinuous spell-out takes place, i.e. the wh-phrase is deleted in the lower copy,

while the noun is given a null spell-out in the upper copy.

According to Rutkowski (2007b), Bošković’s (2005), analysis is questionable as

regards the most recent interpretation of Adjectives. As claimed by Cinque (1994), APs

do not constitute separate functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP

but, instead, they are placed in [Spec; AgrP] position (cf. Chapter 2, section 2.1). In this

analysis they form full constituents and, theoretically, are capable of undergoing

extraction. Therefore the LBE must be blocked not only when AP is not a constituent.

The graphical representation of this analysis is presented in (6) below. For the sake of

simplicity the AgrP is not included within the structure and AP is shown as occupying

[Spec;NP].

(6) Theoretical LBE in DP-languages

(Rutkowski (2007b:57))

background image

63

The second condition on the LBE is also discussed by Bošković (2008).

Following Chomsky’s (2000) reasoning, he claims that a DP, just as a CP, is a phase.

Chomsky (2001) claims that any syntactic operation involves a local relation between a

probe and a goal. A phase is impenetrable in nature, i.e. it blocks the realtion between

an external probe and internal gole. Assuming that a DP is a phase, the LBE is allowed

only if the AP moves outside the DP through the [Spec;DP] position (Bošković (2008)).

This condition is also fulfilled under Rutkowski’s (2007b) analysis. Assuming that an

AP is in the [Spec; AgrP] position it can undergo movement to another Specifier

position: i.e. [Spec; DP]. In articleless languages (e.g. Polish) this position is empty,

therefore the movement is not blocked. On the contrary, in languages with articles, the

[Spec; DP] position is already occupied and movement cannot apply.

What is more, according to Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b), there

are two features of Polish nominal coordination that do not support Bošković’s (2005)

interpretation. NP-external adjectival modification of coordinated phrases and phrasal

coordination at various levels are possible only if we assume the DP analysis of Polish

nominals. Bošković (2005) claims that numerals, just like adjectives and other

modifiers, are NP-internal. This model gives no explanation for the construction

presented in (8) below:

(8)

dziewięciuset profesorów, doktorantów i studentów

nine-hundred professors PhD-students and MA-students

‘nine hundred professors, PhD-students and MA-students’

(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutowski (2007b:113))

background image

64

The phrase in (8) allows one interpretation: ‘there were nine hundred people

altogether: professors, PhD-students and MA-students’ If consistent with Bošković’s

(2005) model, this phrase should have a completely different interpretation, i.e.: ‘there

were nine-hundred professors and some PhD-students and some MA-students’,

however, it cannot be taken into consideration as all the three nominals are assigned

genitive by the numeral. This fact suggests that the numeral must be NP-external

(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007a)).

What is more, Bošković’s (2005) analysis gives no explanation for the examples

of coordination at various levels given bellow:


(9)

a. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and linguists.’

b. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i niemieckich lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and German linguists.’

c. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i wspaniałych niemieckich lingwistek
these five good Polish policewomen and excellent German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and excellent German linguists.’

d.

te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i siedem wspaniałych niemieckich lingwistek

these five good Polish policewomen and seven excellent German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and seven excellent German linguists.’

e. te piec dobrych polskich policjantek i tamte siedem wspaniałych
these five good Polish policewomen and those seven excellent
niemieckich lingwistek
German linguists
‘these five good Polish policewomen and those seven excellent German
linguists.’

(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b;115))

According to Bošković (2005), these phrases are not phrasal constituents and,

therefore, it should not be possible for them to be coordinated. However, assuming the

background image

65

DP interpretation of nominals, we obtain a number of phrasal levels, that allow

coordination. In this model, the following interpretation of examples in (9) is made:

(10) a.

[DP [NumP [AgrP-EVALUATION [_P-ORIGIN [ConjP]]]]]  NP coordination

b. [DP [NumP [AgrP-EVALUATION [ConjP]]]]  AgrP-ORIGIN coordination

c.[DP [NumP [ConjP]]]  AgrP-EVALUATION coordination
d. [DP [ConjP]] NumP coordination

e. [ConjP] DP coordination

(Linde-Usiekniewicz and Rutkowski (2007b:115))

3.1.2 Double genitive constructions

According to Willim (2000), there are two positions within the DP structure of nominals

in which genitive can be assigned, i.e. the complement of NP and Specifier of DP. In

Polish, however, the nominal construction with two genitives is ungrammatical, as

shown below:

(11) *odkrycie Ameryki Kolumba

discovery America-GEN Columbus-GEN

‘the discovery of America by Columbus’

(Rutkowski (2007b:66))

Willim (2000) claims that this is a strong argument against analyzing articleless

languages as DP-languages. This lack of a DP layer makes a double genitive

construction impossible. At the same time similar examples taken from Russian, also an

articleless language, are perfectly grammatical (Engelhardt and Trugman (1998))

(12)

analiz poèmy Puškina literaturoveda

analysis (of) poem Puskin-GEN literary scholar-GEN

‘the analysis of Pushkin’s poem by literary scholar’

(Rutkowski (2007b:67) after Engelhardt and Trugman (1998))

background image

66

As can be seen in (12), Russian allows double genitive constructions, therefore,

according to Engelhardt and Trugman (1998), this is a strong argument for introducing

the DP analysis. Aspiring to forming a universal model of language structure induces us

to apply the same theory to Polish and other articleless languages. Therefore, we may

accept the analysis of Longobardi (2001), who claims that genitive case assignment is

not strictly connected to the D position, but it is generated lower within the functional

layer between a DP and an NP. This allows us to assume that the existence of double

genitive construction is subject to parametric restrictions, various for different

languages.

3.1.3 The Lack of N-to-D movement

According to Longobardi (1994), N-to-D movement is one of the arguments for

postulating the existence of the DP layer in English and the explanation of the Italian

word order within nominal phrases. Italian nominals show a reversed order of

Adjectives toward the Noun in the case of referential expressions like proper names.

(13) a. *E’ venuto vecchio Cameresi.

Come-pasti-3

rd

sing older Cameresi

‘Came older Cameresi’

b. E’venuto Cameresi vecchio

Come-pasti-3

rd

sing Cameresi older

‘Came older Cameresi’

c. E’venuto il Cameresi vecchio

Come-pasti-3

rd

the sing Cameresi older

‘Came the older Cameresi’

(Longobardi (1994:18))

As can be seen from the examples above, Italian recquires Noun-Adjective order in

referential constructions with proper names. The explanation given by Longobardi

background image

67

(1994) assumes that the functional position D cannot stay unfilled when the nominal

phrase has a definite reference. The requirement is fulfilled by the N-to-D movement of

the proper name, as illustrated in (14) below:

(14)

(Rutkowski (2007b;31))

A similar movement appears in other languages, for instance, in English – the

case of someone, anyone, etc. (Abney (1987)) (cf . Chapter 1, example (22) and its

explanation), or in Romanian definite nominal phrases with articles cliticized on nouns

as shown below (Rutkowski (2007b) after Dobrovie-Sorin (1987) and Grosu (1988)).

(15) băiat

i

-ul frumos t

i

boy

i

-art-def nice t

i

‘the nice boy’

According to Willim (2000) the lack of overt N-to-D movement in the Polish

language is another argument against applying the DP Hypothesis to Polish nominals.

The construction as Carmenesi stary - ‘Carmenesi old’ is ungrammatical, accepted only

when used in poetry, which does not show the typical rules of grammar.

background image

68

However, as has already been mentioned in the previous chapter (cf. Chapter 2,

section 2.4) N-to-D movement applies not only to Nouns but also to Pronouns and

Quantifiers. As has been shown in examples (16) and (17), taken from Rutkowski

(2002c), movement to the D position in Polish does exist. Similar observations were

made by Progovac (1998) with respect to another articleless language, Serbo-Croatian.

(16) a. I samu Mariju to nervira.

and alone Marija this irritate.

‘This irritates even Mary’

b. I nju, mene samu to nervira.

and Her,me alone this irritates

‘This irritates even her’

(Progovac (1998:83-84))

In Serbo-Croatian pronouns, being similar to Nouns in their features, originate in

the same position as Nouns, i.e. N

0

. Later on, due to the referential difference, they are

moved to the D

0

position. The adjective, placed in the middle between a DP and an NP,

stays in one place. The movement of the pronoun can be explained only under the DP

analysis of nominals.

3.1.4 Other arguments against the DP analysis of Polish nominals

As has been shown in sections 3.1.1 to 3.1.3 of this chapter, initially irrefutable

arguments against the DP interpretation of nominal phrases in articleless languages do

not hold when contrasted with the language data. The crowning argument of the DP

opponents is the lack of articles in languages like Polish. However, this argument is also

to be invalidated.

background image

69

According to Migdalski (2000), the case of the whole phrase is strictly

connected to the phrase referential aspect. Thus, genitive constructions represent the

indefinite reference, whilst accusative constructions – definite. In this respect, the dative

construction fulfils similar function as the quantifier trochę ‘a bit’ (Rutkowski (2007b)).

The data confirming this thesis are shown in (17) below.

(17) a. Zapakowałem mąki

pack-past-1

st

sing flour-DAT

‘I packed flour.’

b. Zapakowałem mąkę.

pack- past-1

st

sing flour- ACC

‘I packed the flour’

(Rutkowski (2007b:73))

Another argument against the existence of a DP layer in articleless languages is

mentioned by Willim (2000) - i.e. a similarity between demonstratives and adjectives,

that makes the former unable to fill the D

0

position. However, in the light of the newest

interpretation of the position of Demonstratives and Possessives (Brugè (2002), Giusti

(2002), Julien (2002), Roehers (2006), Rutkowski (2007b), among others) this

similarity provides support for the DP Hypothesis. In fact, elements belonging to both

groups, demonstratives and possessives, are derived within the lower parts of the

functional layer of nominal expressions and later they are moved leftwards, respectively

to the [Spec;DP] and [Spec;PossP] position (this movement and the structure will be

discussed in detail in section 3.2.3 of this chapter). The P-maker presenting the structure

is shown below (cf. Chapter 2, section 2.7, (29)):

background image

70

(18)

(Rutkowski (2007b:265))

3.2 The internal structure of nominal phrases in Polish

As has been proved in the previous section of this chapter, the DP analysis of

nominal phrases in languages like Polish is highly motivated by language data. The lack

of articles, i.e. the overt instantiations of the functional D in a language, is not an

argument that refutes the need for postulating the existence of functional projections

heading nominals. In this section I will prove that postulating these projections in Polish

is syntactically adequate and necessary.

DEMONSTRATIVE

NOUN

POSSESIVE

background image

71

At the end of Chapter 2 (cf. (29)) I have presented the structure, which I will

make the basis of the further analysis of Polish language data. I have accepted the

following functional projections:

1. Determiner Phrase – the landing site for Demonstratives and Pronouns, the

basic position of Determiners;

2. Possessive Phrase – the landing site for Possessives;

3. Quantifier Phrase – the basic position of Quantifiers;

4. Agreement Phrases – a series of functional phrases hosting Adjective

Phrases in the position of [Spec;AgrP];

5. n Phrase – the landing site for a Noun, and the basic position of Possesives.

Aiming toward the universality of grammar we must assume that the same

structure applies to other languages, also those articleless.

(19)

Już przyszło [

DP

tych [

PossP

waszych

i

[

QP

pięciu [

AgrP

zdolnych [

nP

t

i

[

NP

uczniów]]]]]].

Already come-past- 3

rd

pl this-pl-ACC your-pl-ACC five-ACC talented-pl-ACC student-pl-ACC.

‘Those five talented students of yours have already come.’

As can be seen in (19), Polish nominal phrases may appear with all the positions

filled. However, it is necessary to analyze Polish data that are similar to the data taken

from other languages, which were the basis for deriving the structure given in Chapter 2

in (29).

background image

72

3.2.1. Noun – pronoun asymmetry. The position of personal pronouns.

The syntactic status of pronouns is rather ambiguous (Rutkowski (2007b)). According

to Progovac (1998), although pronouns appear in the DP-initial position within the

surface structure, in deep structure in fact they originate in the same positions as nouns.

This seems to be confirmed by the coordination of phrases with a Pronoun and with a

Noun, as shown in (20) below.

(20) a. To zrobili [oni wszyscy] i [tamten chłopak]

this do-past-3

rd

pl- masc. [they all] and [that boy].

‘All of them with that boy did it’

However, there are still data, presented by Rutkowski (2007b), that escape an

explanation.

(21)

a. Cały ty!

all you

‘That’s like you!’

b. Cały Cezary!

all Cezary
‘That’s like Cezary!’

c. *Ty cały!

you all
‘That’s like you!

(Rutkowski (2007b: 86))

As can be seen in (21) not in each case Pronouns must be moved to the D

position. According to Longobardi (2006) and Rutkowski (2007b), only Pronouns that

are the arguments of the predicate undergo N-to-D movement. In the case of examples

(21 a-c), due to the fact that the nominal expressions are not arguments, the movement

does not take place. At the same time the data constitute an argument for the N-to-D

movement analysis as they show the original position of Pronouns.

background image

73

3.2.2. Adjectives

One of the most interesting points of Slavic syntax are the Adjectives. In comparison to

other languages e.g. English, they do not show strict hierarchy (cf. Chapter 2, exaple

(19)). According to Rutkowski (2007), it is the semantic context that determines the

grammaticality of the phrase.

(22) a. czarny amerykański samochód

black American car

b. amerykański czarny samochód

American black car

(Rutkowski (2007b:136))

According to Scott’s (2002) hierarchy, only the phrase in (22a) is expected to be

grammatical. However, Rutkowski (2007b), after Bosque and Picallo (1996), declares

both examples grammatical, giving them as examples of subspecification – the

cognitive hierarchization of information. The difference between the two phrases lies in

the semantic scope of both adjectives. Therefore, it changes with the context. The

meaning of the two phrases is given in (23) below:

(23) a. one of American cars, which is black

b. one of black cars, which is American

The more specific is the semantic information carried by an Adjective, the closer

to the modified Noun the Adjective appears. Because of this fact, there is no explicit

way to formulate a constant hierarchy of Adjective Phrases within Polish DPs.

Therefore, Rutkowski (2007b) proposes, after Julien (2002) and Pereltsvaig (2007), to

mark each functional phrase hosting an AP in the position of Specifier as αP (cf. AgrP

in Chapter 2, section 2.4) , as shown in (24):

background image

74

(24) DP

D

αP

AP

α’

α

NP

N

0

(Rutkowski (2007b:130))

However, there is another phenomenon worth mentioning connected to Polish

adjectives: the existence of classifying or classificatory adjectives.

(25) a. gramatyka generatywna

generative grammar

b. piłka nożna
football

c. drzwi przeciwpożarowe

emergenct exit

(Rutkowski (2007b:144))

As can be seen in (25) not all adjectives appear prenominally in Polish. The

classifying Adjectives, which appear postnominally, are closely related to the Noun they

modify and they denote permanent, fundamental and distinctive feature of the Noun

(Rutkowski (2007b)). What is more, they all share other common properties:

1. They do not possess comparative and superlative: *garmatyka generatywniejsza

‘more generative grammar’, *gramatyka najgeneratywniejsza ‘the most

generative grammar’;

2. They cannot be coordinated: *gramatyka i nauka generatywna ‘generative

grammar and science’;

background image

75

3. They do not appear in predicates: *Gramatyka jest generatywna. ‘The grammar

is generative’.

4. They are often generated from nouns: noga ’foot, leg’ - nożna ‘foot-operated’

Worth mentioning is also the fact, that some Adjectives functioning as classifying

adjectives may also appear as ordinary, descriptive adjectives. Then, they appear

prenominally (Rutkowski and Progovac (2005)).

(26) a. biedni ludzie [descriptive interpretation]

poor people

b. ludzie biedni

[classifying interpretation]

the poor

(27) a. obcy jezyk

[descriptive interpretation]

unknown language

b. język obcy

[classifying interpretation]

foreign language

(Rutkowski (2007b:147))

The data in (26) and (27) show adjectives in their both possible interpretations:

classifyng and descriptive. What is more, they suggest the interpretation of their

syntactic structure. Due to the fact that proclaiming the existence of two different

syntactic positions for one adjective would violate the economy condition postulated by

Chomsky (1995a), we may assume that the adjective has just one basic position, and the

movement of one element appears. According to the data presented by Rutkowski

(2007b), it is possible to claim only the movement of a Noun.

(28) a. straszny tygrys

‘fierce tiger’

b. straszny tygrys syberyjski

‘fierce Siberian tiger’

c. *tygrys straszny syberyjski

‘fierce Siberian tiger’

background image

76

d. *tygrys syberyjski straszny

‘fierce Syberian tiger

(Rutkowski (2007b:162))

As can be seen in (28) adjectives in Polish appear mostly prenominally, only

classifying adjectives may appear post nominally. What is more, it is possible to use

only one classifying adjective at once. Therefore according to Rutkowski (2007b), the

classifying adjective appears within the NP, which explains its close relation to the

Noun. The NP is a complement of a Classification Phrase (ClassP) (Rutkowski and

Progovac (2005)), the head of which (Classification – Class

0

) functions as a landing site

for the moved noun (Rutkowski and Progovac (2005)). The whole structure, based on

the data from (28) is presented in (29) below.

(29)

(Rutkowski (2007b:163))

The only problem raised by Rutkowski and Progovac’s (2005) proposal is that

there is no cross-linguistic fact confirming the existence of the ClassP, which is

considered to appear only in Polish. Therefore, according to Rutkowski (2007b), it is

tygrys

i

syberyjski

background image

77

possible to claim that a ClassP is in fact the same projection as an nP (cf. Chapter 2,

section 2.5), which according to recent analyses, is closest to the NP. Then the

movement of the Noun to the n position within the classifying construction corresponds

to the movement of a verb within double object constructions. The new structure is

given in (30).

(30)

(Rutkowski (2007b:178))

3.2.3. Possessive and demonstrative pronouns

Possessives and Demonstratives commonly appear in the initial positions within the

nominal phrase. Therefore, they are usually placed in the position within the two highest

projections: DP and PossP (cf. Chapter 2, structure (29). However, according to Gedeon

(2004), they must derive from the lower parts of the DP.

tygrys

i

syberyjski

background image

78

Assuming that Possessive pronouns are the genitival realizations of personal

pronouns, Gedeon (2004) claims they must be generated within a DP complement of N,

in order to obtain the case. Later on they undergo extraction and are moved to the Poss

0

position. The structure is given below.

(31) a. joho brat

[Ukrainian]

his brother

b.

(Rutkowski (2007b:275))

According to Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004), in Greek demonstrative and

possessive pronouns are generated just above the NP, due to this fact they may be freely

moved leftwards to PossP and DP. The data in (32) seem to confirm this claim.

background image

79

(32) a. afta ta neo fenomena

this-pl the new phenonena

‘these new phenomena’

b. ta nea afta fenomena
the new this-pl phenomena
‘’these new phenomena’

(Rutkowski (2007b:262) after Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004))

As can be observed in (32), Greek demonstratives may appear in two positions:

DP initially (derived after movement) and in strict neighborhood of the Noun (original)

(for the structure cf. (18)) According to Grohmann and Panagiotidis (2004), the

difference between these two positions is not only syntactic but also semantic: the first

one provides deictic reading whilst the second one corresponds to anaphoric.

3.3 The structure of Polish nominal phrases

Polish is a language allowing a reasonably free word order especially as far as

adjectives are concerned. However, it is still possible to distinguish the hierarchy of

main elements appearing within nominal phrases. To account for this fact we must

accept the DP analysis of nominals allowing the existence of functional layers. In the

previous sections of this chapter I presented the necessity of proclaiming the existence

of the Determiner Phrase together with other functional projections in Polish. The order

of which is as follows:

(33) DP > PossP > QP > αP > … > αP > DemP > nP > NP with classifying AP

The construction accounting for all most important language data is presented

below:

background image

80

(34) a. ten nasz jeden wielki biały niedźwiedź polarny

this our one big white polar bear

b. DP

Spec D’

D PossP

Poss QP

Q

αP

AP

α’

α αP

AP α’

α DemP

Dem nP

n

NP

AP N’ GEN

N

DP

ten

i

nasz

j

jeden wielki

biały t

i

niedźwiedź

k

polarny t

k

t

j

background image

81

As can be seen in (34) above, the surface structure of the noun phrase ten nasz

jeden wielki bialy niedźwiedź polarny is derived by means of movements. The Noun is

moved leftward from N

0

to the n

0

affixal in nature creating the NP – AP order

characteristic for classifying constructions. Before that, the Noun assigns Genitive case

to the DP my/nasz, which is later on moved to its target position in Poss

0

. The last

movement applies to the Demonstrative originating under Dem

0

and moved to the

phrase initial position in [Spec;DP]. The order of descriptive adjectives has been

established on the basis of subspecification, and in this case it is in accordance with

Scott’s (2002) hierarchy of adjectives. Polish lacks elements that could appear under D

0

therefore this position stays unfilled by any overt element.

However, there is one question left without answer. There is no reason given for

the movement of the possessive pronoun nasz and the Demonstrative ten. The existence

of different word order patterns in various languages is not a motivation sufficient for

proclaiming the existence of the movements mentioned above.

Conclusion

In this chapter I have focused on the internal structure of Polish nominals. I have shown

that the crowning arguments in favor of the NP analysis of nominal phrases in this

language are not adequate. The Left Branch Extraction (LBE) can be easily accounted

for by appealing to discontinuous spell-out. What is more, NP-external adjectival

modification of coordinated phrases and phrasal coordination at various levels discredit

background image

82

the LBE as an argument against the DP analysis. Similarly, the ungrammaticality of

double genitive construction does not bear on the NP character of Polish nominal

phrases. Since they are grammatical in other articleless languages, double genitives are

claimed to be subject to parametric restrictions independent of the presence of the DP

layer within a nominal construction. What is more, the absence of articles in languages

like Polish appears to be motivated by the presence of overt morphological case, which,

according to Migdalski (2002), is able to carry the definiteness denotation. Finally, the

presence of the DP layer is confirmed by the existence of N-to-D movement in

articleless languages, which is manifested by the reversed order of Adjectives with

respect to pronouns, i.e. only with Pronouns descriptive adjectives appear post-

nominally.

As far as the very internal structure of the DP in Polish is concerned, the

structure does not strikingly stray from the universal structure of DPs presented in the

previous chapter. However there are two facts worth mentioning. First of all, in Polish

we may observe two separate kinds of Adjectives that appear in two different positions,

i.e. descriptive and classifying adjectives. Classifying adjectives are strictly connected

to the Noun they modify – they influence the semantic meaning of the nominal head of

the phrase. Therefore, they are claimed to have an NP-internal origin. On the contrary

descriptive adjectives appearing prenominally fill the position of [Spec;αP] and undergo

universal hierarchy dependencies, typical for this class. However, their order may

undergo changes under special interpretational circumstances.

What is more, the notion of movement of Demonstrative and Possessive

pronouns has been hinted at. Possessive pronouns are claimed to originate within the

DP complement of the Noun where they can be assigned case and afterwards they are

background image

83

moved to their surface position in PossP. Similarly, Demonstrative Pronouns showing

the strict agreement with the Noun with respect to person, number and gender must

originate within the DemP appearing closer to the NP than their surface position,

namely [Spec; DP].

background image

84

Summary and conclusions

This dissertation has examined the structure of nominal phrases in English and Polish. It

started with the presentation of the early GB analysis of nominals and continued with

Abney’s (1987) DP Hypothesis and more recent accounts of the DP structure. The main

aims have been:

to reveal the shortcomings of the early GB account of the nominal phrases,

to outline the main assumptions of the DP Hypothesis,

to examine the status of elements intervening between a DP and an NP,

to point out and examine the most important functional projections appearing

within the nominal structure,

to establish the order of the functional projections within a DP,

to analyse and evaluate the arguments against the DP analysis of Polish

nominals,

to examine the application of the DP analysis of nominal phrases for application

to Polish syntax,

to provide a structure capable of capturing all properties of Polish nominal

phrases.

The first part of Chapter 1 focused on the classical GB account of nominals. It

has been shown that although the NP analysis of nominals accounts for the Binary

background image

85

Branching and Singlemotherhood Constraints, it fails to capture all properties of

nominal phrases. The main problems are summarised below:

- Both demonstratives and possessives are considered to be determiners, therefore

there is no explanation for the co-occurrence of possessives and demonstratives

or articles within one phrase.

- The similarity between nominal and verbal phrases is not covered.

- The word order of the elements intervening between an article and a Noun is not

given any justification. All the elements are treated as adjuncts.

- Determiners constitute an exception within lexical and functional elements of a

language as they do not project any further.

The subsequent aim was to present the basic assumptions of Abney’s DP

Hypothesis. It has been shown that a nominal phrase is headed by a functional element

D. The similarities between a clause and a nominal phrase have been demonstrated on

the basis of the existence of an internal Agreement, an introducing Complementizer

and a head-to-head movement appearing both in clausal and nominal constructions.

Furthermore, additional functional projections intervening between a DP and an NP

have been established. The elements traditionally recognised as adjuncts have been

placed within an Adjective Phrase and an Degree Phrase. The fixed word order of

modifiers within a DP has been accounted for on the basis of the specifier – head –

complement order of phrase structure.

background image

86

The main goal of Chapter 2 was to present and examine the most important

functional projections appearing within a DP. The projections discussed in this

dissertation are as follows:

- Agreement Phrase – developed on the basis of Abney’s (1987) analysis of an

AP, a host to [Agr] feature and later an Adjective Phrase;

- Number Phrase – present in Celtic and Semitic languages, is not important for

the analysis of Polish nominals; this projection carries the features of number

and gender and constitutes the landing site for a Noun;

- Quantifier Phrase – a host to Quantifiers, similar to Agreement Phrase;

- Focus Phrase – connected with the order of adjectives, a landing site of an

element which undergoes preposing;

- n Phrase – a nominal shell, as an equivalent of v; the landing site for a Noun;

- Demonstrative Phrase – the initial position of Demonstratives, which are later

on moved to the Specifier position within a DP;

- Possessive Phrase – the landing site of possessive elements originating below

the Noun.

Subsequently, the order of adjectives within a noun phrase has been discussed.

Following Cinque’s (1994) and Scott’s (2002) analyses it has been shown that

adjectives must be placed in a proper position according to their semantic group.

The aim of the second part of Chapter 2 was to analyse the hierarchy of

functional projections within the DP structure. On the basis of examples it has been

established that the little n stays closest to the NP, with exception of Number Phrase in

Celtic and Semitic languages. Higher within the structure are placed Agreement

background image

87

projections hosting adjectives and a Quantifier Phrase. Possessive Phrase is placed

directly below the DP.

The main aim of Chapter 3 was to examine the structure of Polish nominals. In

the first part of the chapter the analysis treating Polish nominal phrases as NPs has been

presented and evaluated. The starting point for this analysis were the differences

between languages with and without articles. However, it has been revealed that the

phenomena, such as, for instance: The Left Branch Extraction or double genitive

cinstructions, considered to function as crucial arguments against the DP interpretation

of Polish noun phrases are also accounted for under the DP analysis.

In the second part of Chapter 3 Rutkowski’s (2007b) DP analysis of Polish

nominal phrases has been presented and recognised as satisfactory. The main

assumptions of this analysis are listed below:

- Although, there is no overt instantiation of articles in the Polish language, Polish

nominals are headed by a functional element D.

- N-to-D movement applies only to Pronouns that are the arguments of the

predicate.

- The Presence of classifying adjectives constitutes an argument for claiming the

existence of nP within Polish noun phrases.

- The agreement between a noun and demonstrative or possessive elements

indicates that the latter originates lower within the structure than the DP

projection.

The final aim of Chapter 3 was to offer the structure of Polish DP. On the basis of

Rutkowski’s (2007b) analysis all the important functional projections and their order

background image

88

have been established. The following phenomena have been taken into consideration:

movements of a Noun, a Demonstrative Pronoun and a Possessive Pronoun, the

existence of two different groups of adjectives. The final structure has been shown not

to stray from the universal structure of DPs.

To conclude, the structure of a DP appears to be as complicated as the structure of a

clause. Most of the research done focuses on a single aspect of the structure or a single

language, therefore, it is difficult to provide an exhaustive universal model of a DP

structure. At the same time the DP analysis has not been accepted as universal and

further works based on the NP approach toward nominals are continuously offered.

background image

89

References

Abney, Stephen P.1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Doctoral

dissertation, The Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

Adger, David. 2003. Core syntax. A Minimalist Approach. Oxford and New York:

Oxford University Press.

Baker, Mark C. 1988. Incorporation: A theory of grammatical function changing.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Baker, Mark C. 1997. Thematic Roles and Syntactic Structure. In Elements of

Grammar. Handbook of Generative Syntax ed. Liliane Haegeman, 73-137.

Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Bhattacharya, Tanmoy. 1998. DP-internal NP movement . In UCL working papers in

linguistics 10, eds. John Harris and Corinne Iten, 225-251. London: Department

of Linguistics and Phonetics, University College London.

Borer, Haigit. 2001. Plurals and Clasifiers. Ms., University of Southern California.

Borer, Haigit. 2005a. Structuring sense: In name only. Oxford and New York: Oxford

University Press.

Borer, Haigit. 2005b. Structuring sense: The normal course of events. Oxford, New

York: Oxford University Press.

Bošković, Željko. 2003. On left branch extraction . In Investigations into formal Slavic

linguistics: contributions of the Fourth European Conference on Formal

Description of Slavic Languages – FDSL IV held at Potsdam University,

background image

90

November 28-30, 2001, eds. Peter Kosta, Joanna Błaszczak, Jens Frasek, Ljudmila

Geist and Marzena Żygis, 543-577. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

Bošković, Željko. 2004. Topicalization, focalization, lexical insertion, and scrambling.

Linguistic Inquiry 35: 613-638.

Bošković, Željko. 2005. On the locality of left branch extraction and the structure of

NP. Studia Linguistica 59: 1-45.

Bošković, Željko. 2008. What will you have, DP or NP? In Proceedings of FASL 6.5: 9-

35.

Bosque, Ignacio and Carme Picallo. 1996. Postnominal adjectives in Spanish DPs.

Journal of Linguistics 32: 349-385.

Brugè, Laura. 2002. The positions of demonstratives in the extended nominal

projection. In Functional structure in DP and IP: The cartography of syntactic

structures, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 15-53. Oxford and New York: Oxford

University Press.

Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language

Semantics 6: 339-405.

Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on nominalization. In Readings in English

Transformational Grammar. eds. Roderick A. Jacob and Peter S. Rosenbaum,

184-221. Waltham: Ginn.

Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Mouton de Gruyter

Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Barriers (Linguistic Inquiry monographs: 13). Cambridge,

Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

background image

91

Chomsky, Noam. 1995a. The minimalist program (Current studies in linguistics: 28).

Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

Chomsky, Noam.1995b. Bare phrase structure . In Government and Binding theory and

the Minimalist Program, ed. Gert Webelhuth, 383-439. Oxford and Cambridge,

Massachusetts: Basil Blackwell.

Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The Framework. In Step by step: Essays

on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik. eds. Roger Martin, David

Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The

Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A Life in Language, ed.

Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts

Institute of Technology Press.

Cinque, Guglielmo. 1994. On the evidence for partial N movement in the Romance DP.

In Paths towards universal grammar: Studies in honor of Richard S. Kayne. eds.

Guglielmo Cinque, Jan Koster, Jean-Yves Pollock, Luigi Rizzi and Raffaella

Zanuttini, 85-110.Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.

Corver, Norbert. 1992. On deriving certain left branch extraction asymmetries: A case

study in parametric syntax. In NELS 22: proceedings of the twenty-second annual

meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, ed. Kimberly Broderick, 67-84.

Amhest: Graduate Linguistics Students Association, University of Massachusetts.

Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen. 1987. A propos de la structure du groupe nominal en roumain.

Rivista di grammatica generativa 12: 123-152.

Duffield, Nigel. 1995. Particles and Projections in Irish Syntax. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

background image

92

Engelhardt, Miriam and Helen Trugman. 1998. D as a source of adnominal genitive in

Russian. In Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics: The Connecticut meeting

1997 (Michigan Slavic materials: 43), eds. Željko Bošković, Steven Franks and

William Snyder, 114-133. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.

Fanselow, Gisbert and Damir Ćavar. 2002. Distributed deletion. In Theoretical

approaches to universals, ed. Artemis Alexiadou, 65-107. Amsterdam,

Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

Fukui, Naoki. 1986. A theory of category projection and its applications. Doctoral

dissertation. The Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

Gedeon, Olexandra. 2004. Ukrainian possessives and the uniqueness of the third person

possessive pronouns. Colloquium Talks. Detroit: Wayne State University.

Giusti, Giuliana. 1991. The categorial status of quantified nominals, Liguistishe

Berichte 136: 438-454.

Giusti, Giuliana. 1994. Heads and Modifiers among Determiners. In Advance in

Romanian Linguistics, Linguistik Aktuell 10, eds. Cinque Guglielmo and Giuliana

Giusti, 103-125. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

Giusti, Giuliana. 1995. A unified structural representation of (abstract) case and article.

Evidence from Germanic. In Studies in comparative Germanic syntax, eds. Hubert

Haider, Susan Olsen and Sten Vikner, 77-93. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Giusti, Giuliana. 1997. The categorial status of determiners. In The new comparative

syntax, ed. Liliane Haegeman, 95-123. London: Longman.

Giusti, Giuliana. 2002. The functional structure of noun phrases: A bare phrase structure

approach. In Functional structure in DP and IP: the cartography of syntactic

background image

93

structures, vol. 1, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 54-90. Oxfordand New York: Oxford

University Press.

Giusti, Giuliana and Nedžad Leko. 1995. On the syntax of quantity expressions in

Bosnian. University of Venice Working Papers in Linguistics 5.2: 23-47.

Grohmann, Kleanthes K. and Phoevos Panagiotidis. 2004. Demonstrative doubling in

Greek. In University of Maryland working papers in linguistics 13, eds. Pritha

Chandra, Tomohiro Fujii, Usama Soltan and Masaya Yoshida, 109-131. College

Park: Department of Linguistics, University of Maryland.

Grosu, Alexander. 1988. On the distribution of genitive phrases in Rumanian.

Linguistics 26: 931- 949.

Haegeman, Liliane. 1997. The New Comparative Syntax. London: Longman.

Haegeman, Liliane and Jacqueline Guéron. 1999. English grammar: A generative

perspective. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

Hammarström, Harald. 2004. Properties of lower numerals and their explanation: a

reply to Paweł Rutkowski. Journal of Universal Language 5.2: 1-20.

Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes, Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2005. Understanding

Minimalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jackendoff, Ray. S. 1977. X’ syntax: A study of phrase structure. Cambridge,

Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

Julien, Marit. 2002. Determiners and word order in Scandinavian DPs. Studia

Linguistica 56: 264-315.

Kim, Ji-yung. 2004. Specific nominals in Chinese and Korean. Language and

Linguistics 5.1: 243-270.

Larson, Richard K. 1987. 'Missing prepositions' and the analysis of English free relative

clauses. Linguistic Inquiry 16: 239-266.

background image

94

Larson, Richard K. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19,

335-391.

Lecko, Nedžad. 1999. Funcional categories and the structure of DP in Bosnian. In

Mechanisms of syntactic change, eds. Mila Dimitrova-Vulchanova and Lars

Hellan, 419- 444. Austin, University of Texas Press.

Linde-Usiekniewicz, Jadwiga. and Paweł Rutkowski. 2007b. NP coordination as a new

argument in the debate on the DP-analysis of Polish. In LSO working papers in

linguistics, vol. 6: Proceedings of WIGL 2006, ed. Blake H. Rodgers, 103-116

Madison: Department of Linguistics, University of Wisconsin-Madison.

Linde-Usiekniewicz, Jadwiga and Pawel Rutkowski. 2007a. Frequency of use of Polish

numerals does not influence their syntax. In Simon Fraser University working

papers in linguistics, vol. 1: Proceedings of the 22nd NorthWest Linguistics

Conference (NWLC22), eds. Nicole Carter, Loreley Hadic-Zabala, Anne Rimrott

and Dennis Ryan Storoshenko, 175-186. Burnaby: SFU Linguistics Graduate

Students’ Association, Simon Fraser University.

Longobardi, Giuseppe. 1994. Reference and proper names: A theory of N-movement in

syntax and Logical Form. Linguistic Inquiry 25: 609-665.

Longobardi, Giuseppe. 2001. The structure of DPs: Some principles, parameters, and

problems. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, eds. Mark Baltin

and Chris Collins, 562-603. Malden, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Longobardi, Giuseppe. 2006. Reference to individuals, person, and the variety of

mapping parameters. Trieste: Uiniversità degli Studi di Trieste.

Lyons, Christopher. 1997. Definiteness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Megerdoomian, Karine. 2008. Parallel Nominal and Verbal Projections. In

Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays in Honor of Jean-Roger

background image

95

Vergnaud, eds. Robert Freidin, Carlos P. Otero and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta, 73-

103. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Press.

Migdalski, Krzysztof. 2000. The Determiner Phrase hypothesis in Polish. MA thesis,

Wrocław: Uniwersytet Wrocławski.

Mohammad, M. 1988. The Sentential Structure of Arabic. Doctoral dissertation,

University of Southern California.

Pereltsvaig, Asya. 2007. The universality of DP: A view from Russian. Studia

Linguistica 61: 59-94.

Progovac, Ljiljana. 1998. Determiner Phrase in a language without determiners.

Journal of Linguistics 34: 165-179.

Radford, Andrew. 1988. Transformational Grammar: A First Course. Cambridge

University Press.

Radford, Aandrew. 1997. Syntactic theory and the structure of English: a minimalist

approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Radford, Andrew. 2000. NP shells. Essex Research Reports in Linguistics 33: 2-20.

Radford, Andrew. 2004. Minimalist Syntax: Exploring the structure of English.

Cambridge : Cambridge University Press.

Ritter, E. 1988. A head-movement approach to construct-state noun phrases. Linguistics

26: 909-929.

Ritter, Elizabeth. 1991. Two functional categories in noun phrases: Evidence from

Modern Hebrew. In Syntax and semantics 25, Perspectives on phrase structure:

Heads and licensing, ed. Susan D. Rothstein, 37-62, San Diego: Academic Press.

background image

96

Ritter, Elizabeth. 1992. Cross-linguistic evidence for number phrase. Canadian Journal

of Linguistics 37: 197-218.

Roehrs, Dorian. 2006. The morpho-syntax of the Germanic noun phrase: Determiners

move into the Determiner Phrase. Doctoral dissertation. Bloomington: Indiana

University.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2000. Składnia polskich grup liczebnikowych: Próba opisu

formalnego. Poradnik Językowy 8: 10-28.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2001. Numeral Phrases in Polish and Estonian. In Proceedings of the

18th Scandinavian Conference of Linguistics 2, eds. Arthur Holmer, Jan-Olof

Svantesson and Åke Viberg, 181-190. Lund: Lund University Press.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002a. The syntax of Quantifier Phrases and the inherent vs.

structural case distinction. Linguistic Research 7.1: 43-74.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002b. Noun/pronoun asymmetries: Evidence in support of the DP

hypothesis in Polish. In ADL'2002: Actes des 7e rencontres de l'atelier des

doctorants en linguistique, eds. Peggy Afuta, Adil El Ghali and François

Toussenel, 91-96. Paris: École Doctorale de Sciences du Langage, Université

Paris 7.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002c. Noun/pronoun asymmetries: Evidence in support of the DP

hypothesis in Polish. Jezikoslovlje 3.1-2: 159-170.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2007a. The syntax of floating intensifiers in Polish and its

implications for the Determiner Phrase hypothesis. In Proceedings of the Thirty-

Second Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, eds. Zhenya Antic,

Molly Babel, Charles Chang, Jisup Hong, Michael Houser, Fang-Chun Liu,

Maziar Toosarvandani and Yao Yao. Berkeley: University of California

background image

97

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2007b. Hipoteza frazy przedimkowej jako narzędzie opisu

składniowego polskich grup imiennych. Doctral dissertation. Warszawa:

Uniwersytet Warszawski.

Rutkowski, Paweł. 2009. Fraza przedimkowa w polszczyźnie. Warszawa: Wydział

Polonistyki Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego.

Rutkowski, Pawel and Ljiljana Progovac. 2005. Classification Projection in Polish and

Serbian: The position and shape of classifying adjectives. In Formal approaches

to Slavic linguistics: The South Carolina meeting 2004, eds. Steven Franks, Frank

Y. Gladney and Mila Tasseva-Kurktchieva, 289-299. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic

Publications.

Scott, Gray-John. 2002. Stacked adjectival modification and the structure of nominal

phrases. In Functional structure in DP and IP: The cartography of syntactic

structures, ed. Guglielmo Cinque, 91-120. Oxford, New York: Oxford University

Press.

Sio, Joanna Ut-seong. 2006. Modification and reference in the Chinese nominal.

Utrecht: LOT – Landelijke Onderzoekschool Taalwetenschap.

Speas, Margaret J. 1990. Phrase structure in natural language. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Szabolcsi, Anna. 1984. The possessor that run away from home. The Linguistic Review

3: 89-102.

Szabolcsi, Anna. 1987. Functional categories in the noun phrase. In Approaches to

Hungarian, Theories and analyses, ed. István Kenesei, 167-189. Szeged: József

Attila Tudományegyetem (JATE).

Szabolcsi, Anna. 1994. The Noun Phrase. In The Syntactic Structure of Hungarian. eds.

Ferenc Kiefer and Katalin E. Kiss, 179-274. San Diego and New York; Academic

Press.

background image

98

Travis, Lisa. 1992. Inner Tense with NPs: The Position of Number. In 1992 Annual

Conference of the Canadian Linguistics association, 329-345. Toronto: University

of Toronto Working Papers in Linguistics.

Valois, Daniel. 1991. The internal syntax of DP. Doctoral dissertation. Los Angeles:

University of California.

Veselovská, Ludmila. 1995. Phrasal movement and X

0

-morphology: Word order

parallels in Czech and English. Doctoral dissertation. Univerzita Palackého v

Olomouci.

Willim, Ewa. 2000. On the grammar of Polish nominals. In Step by step: Essays on

minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, eds. Roger Martin, David Michaels

and Juan Uriagereka, 319-346. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Massachusetts

Institute of Technology Press.

Yadroff, Michael. 1999. Formal properties of functional categories: The minimalist

syntax of Russian nominal and Prepositional expressions. Doctoral dissertation.

Bloomington: Indiana University.

Zlatić, Larisa. 1997. The structure of the Serbian noun phrase. Doctoral dissertation.

Austin: University of Texas.


Wyszukiwarka

Podobne podstrony:
The Language of Architecture in English and in Polish Jacek Rachfał
Żyto, Kamila Film in the Shadow of History Józef Lejtes and Polish School (2015)
The Role of Vitamin A in Prevention and Corrective Treatments
The Problem Of Order In Society, And The Program Of An Analytical Sociology Talcott Parsons,
Anaphoric Relations in English and Polish
The Spectre of Shakespeare in Rosencrantz and Guildenstern are Dead
KOLE The arrow of time in cosmology and statistical physics (termodynamics, reductionism)
EASE Guidelines for Authors and Translators of Scientific Articles to be Published in English june20
SYNTAX Anaphors in English and the Scope of Binding Theory
Lesley Jeffries Discovering language The structure of modern English
Guide to the properties and uses of detergents in biology and biochemistry
Political Thought of the Age of Enlightenment in France Voltaire, Diderot, Rousseau and Montesquieu
A Comparison of the Status of Women in Classical Athens and E
Industry and the?fects of climate in Italy
The?ll of Germany in World War I and the Treaty of Versail
Pride and Prejudice The Theme of Pride in the Novel

więcej podobnych podstron